P.175
The problem
of personal identity is often said to be
one of accounting for what it is
that gives persons
their identity over time. However, once the problem
has been construed in these terms, it is plain that
too much has already been
assumed. For what has been
assumed is just that persons do have an identity.
To
the philosophers who approach the problem with this
supposition already
accepted, the possibility that
there may be no such thing as personal identity
is
scarcely conceived. As a result, the more
fundamental question--whether
or not personal
identity exists in the first place--remains unasked.
Consequently,
the no-self theory, that is, the
rejection of the notion of personal identity
altogether, is never fully considered. One of the
reasons for the ignoring
of the no-self theory seems
to be the failure of many philosophers to
distinguish between reductionism and the no-self
view. The reasons for this
error are perhaps
understandable. For there is a sense in which the
two
theories are in agreement. Both theories, for
example, reject the notion of
a substantive self
which somehow exists beyond the bounds of
experience.
The difference, however, is that while
the reductionist accounts then go on
to resurrect
the self and, consequently, its identity, in terms
of putative
psychological relations or various
theories of the body, the no-self theory
lets the
self lie where it has fallen. This is because the
no-self theory
is not a theory about the self at
all. It is rather a rejection of all such
theories
as inherently untenable. And since reductionism is
just one more
theory about the self, it, too, must
be untenable. In explaining the distinction
between
these two theories it is instructive to turn to the
philosophy
of mind, where we find a similar
distinction being employed. Here a distinction
is
often drawn between reductive materialism and
eliminative materialism.
Both these theories are in
agreement so far as they reject the existence of
mental phenomena. But while the former attempts to
do so by showing how the
notion of the mental can be
reduced to the physical--that is, that those things
called minds are really just brains or states of the
brain--the latter rejects
the notion of the mental
as fundamentally confused, and so hopes to eliminate
the idea of the mental altogether. The eliminative
materialist would argue
that although the reductive
materialist is right to reject the idea of the
mental, he is wrong to think he can reconstruct the
mental in terms of the
physical. This is because, it
is argued, discourse about things like
intentionality
and awareness is simply not reducible
to discourse about things like neurological
states.
Importing this distinction into the discussion of
personal identity,
we could then say that the
no-self theory is an eliminative rather than a
reductive theory of personal identity. The no-self
critique of the reductive
theory of
P.176
identity would then be that the concept of self and
personal identity cannot
be reduced to our ideas
about psychology or bodies and, therefore, that such
concepts have to be eliminated.(1) We must not,
however, push the analogy
too far. For although some
eliminative materialists see the elimination of
the
theory of the mental as implying an elimination of
mental language,
an analogous implication does not
hold for the no-self theory. That is, within
the
no-self theory we can, as I shall soon argue,
eliminate the notion
of the self and its identity,
and yet on pragmatic grounds continue to permit
the
use of the language of personal identity.
A further but related point that separates
reductionism from the no-self theory
is that since
reductionism seeks to give an account of personal
identity--a
notion which has its roots firmly
embedded in the soil of the strict or nonreductive
theory (that is, the view that personal identity is
something simple and unanalyzable)--then
it has
already accepted a certain view into which it must
now force the
structure of human existence. And
this, it would seem, cannot but lead to
distorted
accounts of how we undergo our experience. The
no-self theory,
on the other hand, has no such prior
commitments. And in this sense it is
more
phenomenologically based than are the reductionist
theories. To borrow
Husserl's phrase, it goes back
to the things themselves. That is, it starts
with an
examination of experience rather than with an
attachment to the
project of how to account for
personal identity. This does not mean, of course,
that the no-self theory need not face the issue of
why someone might come
to believe in his own
identity. For if there is no such thing as personal
identity, then it is essential that we can offer
some other account of why
someone might be led to
think there is.
It is just this sort of approach to the problem
of personal identity that
is found in the writings
of the most important no-self theorist, David Hume.
Hume was the first Western philosopher to unmask the
confusions attending
our idea of personal identity
and subsequently to reject the idea as a fiction.
It
will be worth our while, therefore, to start by
conducting a detailed
examination of his position.
The problem, however, is that there is much
disagreement about how we are to interpret Hume on
this point. On the one
hand, there are some
commentators who, while agreeing that Hume does
reject
the idea of personal identity, go on to
proclaim that his account is deeply
confused and
inconsistent with what he says elsewhere. On the
other hand,
there are those who argue that his
account is quite consistent, but only because
he did
not really reject the notion of personal identity
but only a particular
version of that notion. It
shall be my contention in what follows that both
these accounts are wrong. The latter is wrong
because it fails to accept what
Hume clearly says,
namely, that identity of the self is a fiction. The
former is wrong because it finds confusion and
inconsistency where, if we
are fair to Hume, there
is none. This is not to say that Hume is completely
P.177
clear and
exhaustive in his treatment of personal
identity, but only that within his
writings we have
the makings of a solution to the problem of personal
identity.
What,
then, is Hume's position? If we attend to
the section "Of personal identity"
in Book I or A
Treatise of Human Nature, an answser is immediately
forthcoming.
Hume starts by pointing out that
although some philosophers believe we are
continuously aware of something we call the self,
when We look to our experience
there is nothing to
substantiate this belief. We are never, says Hume,
aware of any constant invariable impression that
could answer to the name
of self. What we
experience, rather, is a continuous flow of
perceptions
that replace one another in rapid
succession. "When I enter most intimately
into what
I call myself," says Hume, "I always stumble on some
particular perception or other, of heat or cold,
light or shade, love or hatred,
pain or pleasure. I
never catch myself at any time without a perception,
and never can observe any thing but the
perception."(2) Within the mind,
he continues, these
perceptions "successively make their appearance;
pass, re-pass, glide away, and mingle in an infinite
variety of postures and
situations" (p. 253). And
there is nothing to the mind but these perceptions.
There is consequently never any simplicity within
the mind at one time nor
identity at two different
times. Nor, says, Hume, do we have any idea of a
self; for every real idea must be derived from some
one impression: "but
self or person is not any one
impression, but that to which our several
impressions and ideas are supposed to have
reference" (p. 251).
With this much said against the notion of
personal identity, Hume turns to
the question of why
we have such a proclivity to ascribe identity to our
successive perceptions. Prefacing his reply to this
question, Hume points
out that a distinction must
first be made between "personal identity
as it
regards our thought or imagination, and as it
regards our passions
or the concern we take in
ourselves" (p. 253). His concern here, he says,
is
with the former. He then starts his answer by
distinguishing between
the ideas of identity and
diversity. In the former case we have the idea of
an
object that persists, invariable and uninterrupted,
through a particular
span of time. It is this that
comprises our idea of identity. In the case
of
diversity we have the "idea of several different
objects existing
in succession, and connected
together by a close relation" (p. 253).
Now although
these two ideas are plainly distinct, it is certain,
says
Hume, that in our "common way of thinking" we
generally confound
them. That is, we often claim
that an object at one time is identical with
an
object at another time, when in fact the two are
little more than a
succession of different objects
connected by a close relation. To justify
these
absurd ascriptions of identity we either come up
with the notion
of a substantive self by feigning
the continued existence of our perceptions,
or we
imagine the existence of something mysterious which
binds our many
P.178
perceptions
together. Even where we do not do this
we at least have a propensity to do
so. We can see,
then, says Hume, that because we often assert the
existence
of such fictions, the problem of personal
identity is not merely a verbal
dispute. It is
natural to ask, therefore, what it is that induces
us mistakenly
to attribute identity to something
while, being a succession of objects, it
is really
an instance of diversity. Hume feels that the
answer must lie
in the workings of the imagination.
The reason why we might make such an attribution,
says Hume, is that "the passage of thought from the
object before the
change to the object after it, is
so smooth and easy, that we scarce perceive
the
transition, and are apt to imagine, that 'tis
nothing but a continu'd
survey of the same object"
(p. 256) . This is especially true when the
alteration is either relatively small or when it
occurs gradually and insensibly.
From here Hume goes on to consider the various
other ways in which we ascribe
identity to objects
which are variable and interrupted. This lays the
ground for his account of personal identity. For the
identity of the mind,
like that of such changing
things as plants, animals, repaired ships, rebuilt
churches, and republics, says Hume, is only a
fictitious identity. It must
therefore be similarly
explicable in terms of the workings of the
imagination.
Hume concludes his account with the
important remark that all "nice and
subtile"
questions concerning personal identity are best
considered
as grammatical rather than philosophical
difficulties. Thus, except where
the notion of a
fictional entity or principle is involved, all
disputes
about personal identity are merely verbal
disputes and can never possibly
be decided.
A hurried
reading of this section of the
Treatise might well lead one to conclude that
Hume
is confused; for there are some apparent
inconsistencies. These difficulties,
however, are
resolved by keeping in mind the scope of Hume's
project and
not allowing his claims to be taken out
of context. Let us start our appraisal
of Hume by
dealing with a criticism raised by one of his
commentators.
In a paper called "Hume on Personal
Identity," Penelhum argues that
Hume's account is
an immense blunder, "an excellent example of how
complex and far-reaching the consequences of a
mistake in linguistic analysis
or conceptual
investigation can be."(3) According to Penelhum,
Hume's
fatal mistake is to think that one object
cannot have many parts. This is
false, claims
Penelhum, because whether or not an object has parts
will
depend upon what sort of object it is. A
melody, for example, is still one
melody even though
it consists of a succession of notes. A related
mistake,
we are told, is Hume's muddling of the
distinction between the numerical and
specific
senses of identity. To remain the same through a
period of time
is to remain the same in a specific
sense: to be exactly the same as one was
at an
earlier time. For an object to change, however, it
must remain numerically
the same; for it must be one
and the same object which is doing the changing.
P.179
Unfortunately
for Penelhum, Hume makes it quite
plain that he does allow for one object
to have many
parts, and he even allows that the parts may undergo
certain
changes without affecting the identity of
the whole:
Suppose any mass of matter, of which the parts
are contiguous and connected,
to be plac'd
before us; 'tis plain we must attribute a
perfect identity
to this mass, provided all the
parts continue uninterruptedly and invariably
the same, whatever the motion or change of place
we may observe either in
the whole or in any of
the parts. (P. 255)
What Hume does not allow is that an object can
maintain its identity with
a coming and going of its
parts. It might seem, however, that this is all
Penelhum needs to have his point go through. For
what is a melody but one
thing which is a succession
of other things? And if this is so, then Hume
would
appear to be wrong in holding that a succession of
objects cannot
be one object.
This,
however, will not sustain Penelhum's
objection. For if a melody is an object,
it is a
different sort of object than are the objects with
which Hume
is concerned. A melody, by definition, is
a temporal sequence of musical notes:
it is
something whose existence is necessarily spread out
over time. It
is therefore logically incapable of
existing instantaneously in the specious
present.
But there are no such logical restrictions on the
existence of
trees, ships, churches, or persons. We
can easily imagine a tree, for instance,
which
suddenly pops into existence only to disappear
immediately. And
we can also imagine, it would seem,
a person who exists but for a second.
It is true
that trees and persons as a matter of fact tend to
exist for
varying durations of time, but I see
nothing logically incoherent about their
existing
merely in the specious present. Indeed, it is just
because our
idea of a person does allow for the
momentary existence of a person that we
are able to
ask questions about personal identity in the first
place.
For only when we have allowed this can we
raise the question of whether a
person existing at
this particular instant is the same as an earlier
person
existing at an earlier instant. We cannot,
however, ask the same question
about a melody, for
melodies do not exist at particular instants; only
their notes do.
So Penelhum's alleged counterexample of one
melody that contains several parts
is quite
acceptable to Hume. It is acceptable, first, because
Hume never
denied that one object cannot consist of
several parts and, secondly, because
even though a
melody is a succession of parts, this is a necessary
feature
of a melody in a way that it is not a
necessary feature of a person.
What about Hume's purported muddling of the
numerical and specific senses
of identity? This
would be a strange error for Hume to make since, as
Penelhum is aware, Hume himself draws this very
distinction in the course
of his argument. But,
according to Penelhum, Hume has made
P.180
this mistake
just so far as he thinks that for
something to remain the same it must not
change. For
an object to remain unchanged is for it to remain
the same
in the specific sense. But for an object to
change through time it must remain
the same in the
numerical sense. Of course, says Penelhum, an object
can
lose its identity by changing, but only if the
object is by definition an
unchanging thing.
It should not be too difficult to see what is
wrong here. Consider Hume's
example of a ship that
has its parts gradually replaced. It is possible
that eventually none of the parts of the original
ship remain. And yet the
ship of today might be
exactly similar to the earlier ship. We can express
this relationship by saying the two ships have a
specific identity; that is,
they exactly resemble
each other. It would be false, however, to say that
the two ships have a numerical identity; for there
is nothing about them that
is numerically the same.
In contrast to this, Penelhum argues that the only
reason for saying that something has lost its
identity (that is, has become
another thing) is that
it is by definition an unchanging thing. Since
nothing in the definition of a ship seems to rule
out the possibility of the
ship having its parts
repaired, then even though the ship of today shares
not one plank or bolt in common with the earlier
ship, the two are nonetheless
numerically identical,
that is, one and the same ship. But were we to
accept this scenario we would immediately be faced
with a difficulty. For
how could we distinguish
between the situation where a ship has persisted
without changing any of its parts, and the very
different situation where
it has changed all of its
parts? The natural way for us to mark this
distinction
would be to say that in the former case
the ship of today is exactly one and
the same as the
earlier ship, while in the latter case it only
resembles
the earlier ship. That is, in the first
case the two ships are numerically
identical, but in
the second case they are only specifically
identical.
But on Penelhum's account we cannot draw
this distinction, because there is
no distinction to
be drawn. Both cases have equal claim to being
instances
of numerical identity. And yet it is
obvious that there is an important distinction
to be
made here. In the case of the unaltered ship, what
we have is a
ship that is identical in the strongest
sense with the earlier ship. In the
case where the
ship suffers a total change of its parts, it can be
the
same as the earlier ship only in a weaker sense
And thin distinction, which
is natural to mate, is
merely the distinction between numerical and
specific
identity. Hume's account of identity
allows us to make this distinction; Penelhum's
does
not. It seems, therefore, that it is Penelhum who
has muddled things.
We should not, however, be led to conclude that
the distinction between numerical
and specific
identity is central to Hume's discussion. For Hume
is not
really interested in specific identity and
only introduces the distinction
by way of showing
how we might come to ascribe (numerical) identity
where
there is none. One such way--and there are
P.181
other ways--is
to confound the ideas of numerical
and specific identity and to claim that
two
successive objects are numerically identical when
they are only specifically
identical.
This,
it seems, is the mistake made by James
Noxon.(4) Noxon tries to argue that
this distinction
lies at the heart of Hume's thesis and that Hume's
real
purpose is to show how identity terms can be
meaningfully applied to persons
once the
numerical/specific distinction is made clear.
But this is an unfounded reading of Hume. For
not only does Hume refer to
the notion of specific
identity only in passing, but also nowhere does he
mention or even imply that the real identity of
these variable and interrupted
things is a specific
identity. If we turn to the quotations cited as
support
for this view, we can see the error
immediately. When Hume says that a seedling
which
becomes a large tree is still the same oak, and that
an infant which
becomes a man is still the same
individual, he cannot be referring to specific
identity; for it is evidently false to say that a
seedling is exactly similar
(that is, specifically
identical) to a one-hundred-foot tree, and just as
false to say that an infant is exactly similar to an
adult. There may be some
vague similarities in
either case, but not enough to justify a claim to
specific identity. Noxon seems aware of this problem
and tries to avoid it
by asserting that specific
identifications are based on "points of resemblance
evaluated in light of general knowledge of the
changes which things of a certain
sort undergo
during a certain period of time."(5) But I am not
even
sure if I know what this means. How is the
knowledge that a seedling will
change into a large
oak supposed to aid us in evaluating points of
resemblance
between the two? For, regardless of our
knowledge of arboreal ontogeny, the
fact remains
that a sprouting acorn bears little or no
resemblance to
a massive oak.
Further,
it seems clear that Hume, in his
examples, is intent on denying similarity
rather
than affirming it. Not only does the tree have no
particles of
matter in common with the seedling, but
even the "figure of its parts
is different.
Likewise, the infant not only grows into an adult,
but is
"sometimes fat, sometimes lean." Noxon could
always protest here
that the tree remains exactly
similar to the seedling so far as it is still
an
oak. But Hume says more than that the tree is still
an oak; he says
it is still the same oak. And this
strongly suggests that he is not here using
"same"
in its specific sense. If he only meant that the
seedling
is as much an oak as the tree (a pointless
thing to say), there would have
been no need for the
insertion of the words "the same" before "oak."
But does this not leave us with a problem? For
if Hume is not here referring
to the specific
identity of the oak, then, we might think, he must
be
referring to its numerical identity; but as we
have just noted, the tree is
said to have not one
particle in common with the seedling, which means,
for Hume, that the two cannot be numerically
identical. The solution to this
problem is to see
that Hume is not referring to the tree's
P.182
identity in
any sense: he is referring to our
attribution of identity to the tree (that
is, our
attribution of numerical identity). This is evident
from the line
which immediately precedes his example
of the tree. Hume remarks here "tho'
everyone must
allow, that in a very few years both vegetables and
animals
endure a total change, yet we still
attribute identity to them, while their
form, size
and substance are entirely alter'd" (p. 257). The
reference
to the growing oak and the growing man are
merely illustrative examples of
a changing plant and
a changing animal to which we attirbute identity.
Since, however, there can be no identity where the
form, size, and substance
of a thing has entirely
altered, the identity which we attribute in such
cases can only be a fictitious one; that is, it is
the work of the imagination,
not a property
belonging to the object or, better, to the
succession of
objects to which we attribute it. And
this is true not just for plants and
animals but for
all things which are variable and interrupted: for
example,
repaired ships, rebuilt churches, rivers,
republics, and persons. So when
Hume discusses "the
identity" of such things, he is only discussing
how
we come to attribute identity to them, not their
actual identity.
The only reason we might think that Hume is
making positive statements about
the actual identity
of things is that we may fail to notice the
structure
of his overall argument and locus only on
specific remarks. If we view the
section "Of
personal identity" as a whole, wee will see that in
the first four paragraphs Hume discusses the actual
identity of the self and
categorically rejects the
notion as untenable. He does, however, feel that
we
have a natural propensity to ascribe identity to
ourselves, and it
is to an explanation of this
propensity that Hume devotes the rest of his
discussion. This division in the test is also
attended, for the most part,
by a division in the
type of language that Hume uses to discuss identity.
In the first part, Hume speaks in a categorical way.
Thus it is claimed, for
example, that "there is no
inmpression constant and invariable"
(p. 251) .
"there is no such idea (of the sell)" (p. 252), "I
always stumble on some particular perception or
other" (p. 252), and,
finally, "there is properly no
simplicity in (the mind) at one time,
nor identity
in different" (p. 253). However, when we come to the
second part of the discussion, the language becomes
more psychological than
categorical. That is, Hume's
concern here is more with how we imagine, suppose,
ascribe, or attribute identity rather than with the
actual identity of things.
And so the second part
begins by asking "What then gives us so great
a
propension to ascribe an identity to these
successive perceptions, and
to suppose oursleves
possest of an invariable and uninterrupted existence
thro' the whole course of our lives?" (p. 253; my
emphasis). This psychological
language continues,
for the most part, throughout this latter half: the
repaired ship "is still consider'd as the same; nor
does the difference
of the materials hinder us from
ascribing an identity to it" (p. 257);
although
P.183
plants and animals undergo a total change, "yet we
still attribute identity
to them" (p. 257); a man
who hears an intermittent noise "says it
is still
the same noise" (p. 258); and because an earlier
church
is demolished before its successor appears we
do not think of them as being
different, "and for
that reason are less scrupulous in calling them the
same" (p. 258; my emphasis throughout the last four
quotations). Likewise,
when Hume says we can extend
our identity beyond our memories, his discussion
makes it plain that he is only talking about "the
most established notions
of personal identity" (p.
262; my emphasis) , that is, what is commonly
believed to be true about personal identity, and not
about personal identity
itself.
This use
of psychological language to discuss
the supposed identity of interrupted
and variable
objects should keep us alert to the fact that Hume
is here
discussing only the origin of our belief in
such identity, and not the actual
identity of what
is really an instance of diversity. Once we see this
we should not be worried by Hume's occasional use of
categorical statements
in what is overtly a
discussion of psychology. Thus, when, in the second
part of the text, Hume states that a seedling which
becomes a tree "is
still the same oak," all that is
before this makes it plain that he can
only mean
that it is still called the same oak, or it is still
supposed
to be the same oak, or some such thing, not
that it is actually still the
same oak. Likewise,
when he says that the infant becomes a man "without
any change in his identity," all that he can mean is
"without our
attributing any change to his
identity."
There will be those, no doubt, who will charge
that I am riding roughshod
over what Hume says and
am twisting the text to suit my own purposes. But
if
this is true, then my critics must explain why Hume
says that although
the addition or removal of even
an inconsiderable amount of a mass of matter
"absolutely destroys the identity of the whole,
strictly speaking; yet
as we seldom think so
accurately, we scruple not to pronounce a mass of
matter the same, where we find so trivial an
alteration" (p. 256). For
in saying this Hume has
not only given the reasons why growing plants and
humans cannot maintain their identity over time
(they are continually losing
and gaining amounts of
matter), but he also explains why we scruple not to
pronounce them the same (we find their
monment-to-moment alterations too trivial
to note).
Of course, over many years the alterations that a
seedling has
undergone will no longer be trivial,
"but where the change is produc'd
gradually and
insensibly we are less apt to ascribe to it the same
effect
(that is, the loss of its identity)" (p.
256).
All of this should make it clear that, contrary
to what many of Hume's interpreters
would have us
believe, for Hume it is an error to attribute
identity to
variable and interrupted things. He says
in several places that the attribution
of identity
to instants of diversity is both a
P.184
mistake and
an absurdity (see especially pp.
254-255). But we must be careful here; for
its being
a mistake does not imply what Penelhum thinks it
does.
After noting Hume's claim that we are making a
mistake in referring to a person
over time as the
same person, Penelhum remarks that "a little effort
of imagination is enough to indicate just how much
chaos would result from
adopting Hume's diagnosis as
the source of a prescription and using a different
proper name whenever we noticed the slightest
change, even in ourselves (or
rather in the separate
people that we would be from minute to minute)."
And
if this is a mistake, continues Penelhum, it is one
whose correction
"would require a complete overhaul
of the concepts and syntax of our
language."(6)
Yet there is no reason to think that the correct
prescription for Hume's diagnosis
need be using a
different proper name every time we notice a change
in
someone or something. Indeed, Hume even says that
a rebuilt church, which
we only imagine to be the
same as an earlier one, can still be called the
same
as its predecessor "without breach of the propriety
of language"
(p. 258). He does not, unfortunately,
elaborate on this. However, at the end
of the
section on personal identity something is said that
suggests how
it might be permissible to call two
things the same which in fact are only
imagined to
be the same. Here Hume states that all disputes
about the
identity of successive objects "are merely
verbal, except so far as the
relation of parts give
rise to some fiction or imaginary (i.e. mysterious)
principle of union" (p. 262). Thus if two persons
are arguing about whether
or not an earlier church
is the same as its rebuilt predecessor, and neither
of them is asserting the existence of a fictional
entity or principle of union
which somehow unites
the two churches, then their dispute will be merely
about how the word "same" is to be used in these
circumstances.
That is, they will not be disputing
an actual identity but only the linguistic
conventions surrounding our use of identity terms.
If we imagine that our
disputants finally agree that
our linguistic conventions permit us to call
the two
churches the same (a conclusion to which Hume would
give his assent),
then we can see why it is
permissible to call two things the same which are
in
fact different This is because there are two levels
at which the notion
of identity can be employed: one
which deals with questions about identity
at the
metaphysical or ultimate level, and one which deals
with them at
the verbal or conventional level.
It is disappointing that Hume does not have more
to say about the two levels
of "disputes." For it is
with such an account that we are able to
explain why
it is acceptable for us to continue to talk in terms
of selves
and personal identity despite the fact
that there are no such things. We can,
however,
arrive at a fuller understanding of what the
two-level account
involves by turning to another
version of the no-self theory. This
P.185
is the no-self
theory as propounded by the Buddha
and various of his followers. The Buddhist
theory
can offer some insights. For at the very heart of
this theory lies
the doctrine of the two levels of
truth. Although the different schools of
Buddhist
thought disagree on the exact nature of the
distinction to be
drawn between the two truths,
there are enough similarities-at least in the
early
Hinayana schools--for us to give a general account.
This will be
useful to our project because it will
allow us both to see what Hume might
have been
getting at and to acquire more munitions with which
to fend
off this attack on the no-self theory.
I hasten to add, however, that I am
not here
attempting a scholarly exposition of Buddhist
thought; for my
present interests are confined to an
exposition of the no-self theory of personal
identity. It is just that Buddhism has some valuable
contributions to make
here. There are, of course,
problems involved in the cross-cultural discussion
of ideas; Hume and the Buddha, after all, lived
their lives in very different
social and historical
contexts. And yet I do not think that these
difficulties
need detain us; for when we go to the
texts where Buddhist thinkers are grappling
with the
problem of personal identity, we find their concerns
are essentially
the same as Hume's.
In the earliest texts of Buddhism, the Pali
Canon (about 500 B.C.), we come
across a distinction
drawn between two types of discourse: that of direct
meaning and that of indirect meaning. The former
type of discourse is said
to be one whose meaning is
plain while the latter type needs to have its
meaning inferred with reference to the former. In
the discourses of indirect
meaning, words are used
which apparently refer to persisting entities such
as a self or an I which, according to the Buddha,
are merely "expressions,
turns of speech,
designations in common use in the world which the
Tathagata
(i.e, the Buddha) makes use of without
being led astray by them."(7)
That is, although we
may use words like "self" and "I,"
we should not be
led into thinking that they actually refer to
something,
for they are but grammatical devices.
This nondenoting aspect of these expressions
is
something which must be inferred in light of the
discourses of direct
meaning. In this latter type of
discourse, the nonexistence of anything permanent
or
enduring, such as the self or I, is asserted, and
the misleading features
of language--those features
which lead us astray into the belief in an I--are
made explicit. Here there is no need for inference,
since the meaning of such
discourse is plain.
As it happens, however, we are apt to confuse
the two types of discourse:
"there are these two who
misrepresent the Tathagata. Which two? He who
represents a Sutta (i.e., discourse) of indirect
meaning as a Sutta of direct
meaning and he who
represents a Sutta of direct meaning as a Sutta of
indirect meaning."(8) Although the Pali Canon does
not elaborate here,
we can easily see what sorts of
errors are being referred to. On the one hand
we
might think that someone who is using the
P.186
words "self,"
"I,"or "Buddha" (which are mere turns
of speech) is in
fact denoting a particular entity.
Or, on the other hand, we might think that
someone
who is denying the existence of the self cannot
really mean what
he or she is saying and so we might
be tempted to infer a further meaning
which would
still allow the existence of the self. We might, for
instance,
think that the person making this claim is
only denying the existence of a
certain type of
self.
The discussion of the two types of discourse is
continued in the various Buddhist
commentaries on
the Pali Canon, and here we are introduced to the
related
ideas of two levels of truth. In one
commentary it is stated that all "Buddhas
(i.e.,
enlightened beings) have two types of speech;
conventional and
ultimate. Thus 'being', 'man',
'person', (the proper names) `Tissa', 'Naga'
are
used as conventional speech. `Cagegories',
'elements', 'sense-bases'
are used as ultimate
speech." Because of this division in speech, we
are
told that the Buddha "declared two truths: the
conventional and
ultimate, there is no third. Words
(used by) mutual agreement are true because
of
Worldly convention; words of ultimate meaning are
true because of the
existence of elements."(9)
Although the various elements are said to
be the
constituents of which everything else, including
what we call the
self, is made, it is not because
the elements are more basic than the self
that the
self is said ultimately not to exist. It is simply
because there
is nothing in the world, not even an
assemblage of the elements, that can
be identified
with the self. Although the Buddha cites various
characteristics
that something must have if it is to
be considered a self, the most important
is that of
permanence or identity over time. But when we look
to our experience,
there is nothing but impermance:
our bodies, feelings, and thoughts are forever
coming and going. In this sense the Buddha is in
complete agreement with Hume:
where there is
diversity there can be no identity. None of this,
however,
implies that statements which make use of
words like "self," "I,"
"you." " "Tissa, " or
"Buddha.' are false or
nonsensical at every level of
discourse. For they can be true at the conventional
level, which means that they can be true because of
their being used in accordance
with mutual
agreement, that is, linguistic convention.
A good illustration of how this distinction is
to be drawn is given in a well-known
passage from
the The Questions of King Menander (about A.D.
100).(10)
In this dialogue, the Indo-Greek king
Menander puts various questions about
the nature of
the self to the Buddhist monk Nagasena. At the
opening of
the dialogue, Menander asks "How is your
Reverence known, and what is
your name? " The
somewhat provocative answer given to the king is
"I'm known as Nagasena, your Majesty, that's what my
fellow monks call
me. But though my parents may have
given me such a name... it's only a generally
understood term, a practical designation. There is
no question of a permanent
individual implied in the
use
P.187
of the
word." Menander is quite astonished by this
reply and eventually asks
"If your fellow monks call
you Nagasena, what then is Nagasena?"
He asks
whether Nagasena is any part of the body or the
mind, or whether
he is all of these things taken
together, or whether he is anything apart
from them.
To all of this Nagasena replies merely "No, your
Majesty."
Menander then exclaims triumphantly "Then
for all my asking find no Nagasena.
Nagasena is a
mere sound! Surely what your Reverence has said is
false!"
But Nagasena is not to be dealt with so
swiftly and, in good Socratic fashion,
replies by
himself asking a question: "Your Majesty, how did
you
come here--on foot, or in a vehicle?" "In a
chariot," says
Menander. Nagasena then asks what the
chariot is, whether it is the pole,
axle, wheels,
frame, reins, or yoke, or whether it is all these
taken
together, or again whether it is something
other than the separate parts.
Menander replies in
the negative. With this Nagasena fires back at the
king his own reasoning: "Then for all my asking,
your Majesty, I can
find no chariot. The chariot is
merely a sound. What then is the chariot?
Surely
what your Majesty has said is false! There is no
chariot!"
Menander protests that he has not said
anything false: "It's on account
of all these
various components, the pole, axle, wheels, and so
on, that
the vehicle is called a chariot. It's just
a generally understood term, a
practical
designation." Nagasena's rejoinder is to praise
Menander
for this remark and to point out that the
same holds true of himself. For
it is because of his
various components that he is known by the practical
designation "Nagasena." However, he adds, in the
ultimate sense
there is no person to whom the name
refers.
It is easy to mistake this passage, as some have
done, for a statement of
reductionism.(11) But the text
clearly disallows this interpretation. The
reductionist view would be that the person of
Nagasena can be reduced without
remainder to his
various impersonal constituents. But when the king
asks
if Nagasena is all of the parts of his body and
mind taken together, Nagasena
answers "No." This is
because Nagasena rejects any notion of a person
that
exists in the ultimate sense: a person is not
ultimately something
other than his parts (the
strict theory), nor is a person ultimately the sum
of his parts (the reductionist theory). This does
not mean, however, that
the word "Nagasena" is a
mere sound; for it is more than that: it
is a
generally understood term whose proper use is
determined by mutual
agreement concerning how, when,
and where it is to be used. Or, as Nagasena
says, it
is because of his various components that he is
known as "Nagasena,"
even though "Nagasena" does not
refer to anything.
It is crucial to see, however, that in
relegating such terms to the realms
of conventional
discourse, Buddhism is nor proposing a
conventionalist
theory of personal identity. That
is, for Buddhism, a person's identity is
not
something ultimately to be decided by convention.
For to
P.188
hold this
position would be to commit the very error
against which the Pali Canon warns
us, that is, to
represent a discourse of indirect meaning as a
discourse
of direct meaning. It would be to conflate
the levels of truth and think that
questions at the
ultimate level can be answered by agreements at the
conventional
level.
We are now
able to see why the no-self theory
does not imply that our language is in
need of an
overhaul. For it is quite consistent with the
nonexistence
of the self or I that we continue to
employ the words "sell" and
"I" in their practical
everyday usage, provided we do not mistake
them for
denoting some particular entity at the ultimate
level, or, as
Hume would say, feign the existence of
a fiction. This is why, contrary to
what many of
Hume's critics think, Hume's own use of the
first-person
pronoun does not undermine his theory.
In Hume's statement "when I enter
most intimately
into what I call myself, I always stumble on some
particular
perception" (p. 252), the word "I" is
being used at the convectional
level: it is merely a
generally understood term whose proper use is
determined
by mutual agreement. We should not,
therefore, think that in using the first-person
pronoun Hume has committed himself to the existence
of a self at the ultimate
level.
Some will
no doubt find it paradoxical that we
can use personal language correctly when
there is
nothing to which these terms ultimately refer. It
was reasoning
akin to this, it seems, that led
Descartes to his famous proclamation "I
think,
therefore I am." I must exist, reasoned Descartes,
because
even when I doubt that I exist there is
still an I that is doing the doubting.
But Descartes
has become led astray by his own language, for there
is
no need for the "I" in "I think" or "I doubt" to
refer to anything. What Descartes was aware of, as
both Hume and the Buddha
would agree, was just
thinking, not an I that was doing the thinking.
Consequently Descartes might just as well have said
(and should have said
if his concern was with
ultimate rather than conventional truth) "there
is
thinking, therefore there are thoughts." And such a
deduction,
if we may call it that, does not suffice
to prove the existence of an I.
A possible response here would be to say that
although there need be no reference
to an I when we
use the nounal sense of "thinking" or "thoughts,"
when the verbal sense "I think" is employed, then
plainly there
must be some reference to a subject;
for what is it that thinks? To this it
can be
replied that although the term "think" does require
a
subject, this is little more than a grammatical
requirement. And so we might
just as well employ a
nonreferring grammatical subject rather than the
misleading term "I." This is a point that is
recognized by George
Christoph Lichtenberg, who
says, about Descartes' dictum, "We should
say,'It
thinks', just as we say 'It thunders'. Even to say
cogito is too
much if we translate it with 'I
think'. To assume the 'I' to postulate it
is a
practical need."(12) Thus, since the use of the
verbal sense
"thunders" also
P.189
requires the
introduction of a subject, we bring in
the word "it" and say "it
thunders." But this does
not mean that the grammatical subject "it"
here
refers to anything. All we are saying when we say
"it thunders"
is "there is thunder." Consequently,
since the requirement that
the word "thinks" have a
subject is also a convention of grammar,
or, as we
might say with Lichtenberg, a practical need, we
could likewise
employ "it" to serve this purpose. We
could say "it thinks,
therefore there are thoughts,"
and the appearance of "it" here
would no more imply
a reference to an actual subject than would "it"
in
"it thunders."(13)
There remains, however, a further problem which
needs our attention. It was
mentioned earlier that
one of the criticisms leveled at Hume is that his
account of personal identity is inconsistent with
what he says elsewhere.
The passages which are
supposed to contradict the view of the section on
personal identity come from Book II of the Treatise,
where in Hume discusses
the nature of the passions
or emotions.(14) Because Hume refers here to the
importance of the role played by the self as the
object of such passions as
pride and humility, some
writers have been quick to accuse him of
contradicting
his earlier claims about the self.
Thus Norman Kemp Smith cites the following
passages
from Book II as being incompatible with Hume's
claims from Book
I:
'Tis evident,
that the idea, or rather
impression of ourselves is always intimately
present with us, and that our consciousness
gives us so lively a conception
of our own
person, that 'tis not possible to imagine, that
any thing can
in this particular go beyond it.
(P. 317)
The stronger the relation is betwixt ourselves
and any object, the more easily
does the
imagination make the transition, and convey to
the related idea,
the vivacity of conception,
with which we always form the idea of our own
person. (P. 318)(15)
Kemp Smith suggests that the reason why Hume so
freely makes use of the idea
of the self in Book II
when he has just dismissed the notion in Book I is
that Book II was written before Book I, and,
consequently, by the time Hume
had got around to
writing Book I he had forgotten what he had said in
Book II.(16) Before we accept this picture of a
strangely distracted Hume,
it seems we should look
at what is actually being said about the self in
Book II. And what we find in the opening pages of
Book II is this: "`Tis
evident, that pride and
humility, tho' directly contrary, have yet the same
object. This object is the self, or that succession
of related ideas and impressions,
of which we have
an intimate memory and consciousness." And a few
lines later we are told about "that connected
succession of perceptions,
which we call self" (p.
277). These hardly seem like the words of someone
who is totally incognizant of the view expressed in
the section on personal
identity. Indeed, by taking
the time to insert these descriptions of the self
in
Book II, it seems that Hume is
P.190
anxious to
remind us of the conclusions reached in
Book I. And so, when Hume says in
Book II that an
awareness of ourselves is always intimately present
to
us, we should understand this in terms of what
was said in Book I, namely,
that to enter intimately
into what is called the self is just to encounter
various impressions. That is, what is always
intimately present to us is just
those particular
perceptions whose succession we call the self (the
fact
that Hume uses the word "intimately" in both
the passages from Book
I and Book II also suggests
that he is intent on discussing the same notion
of
the self in both places).
Still there is an apparent problem here. And
this is highlighted by the fact
that Hume often
speaks in Book II of our idea or impression of the
self
as though it were something which occurs
instantaneously within our awareness,
a singular
perception which we experience as the object of
pride and humility.
But, as Hume has told us, there
is no impression or idea of the self; there
is only
the smooth and uninterrupted progress of thought
within our imagination.
But how is it that a smooth
and uninterrupted progress of thought could appear
instantaneously within awareness? The notion of an
uninterrupted progress
is a temporal notion; it is
something that occurs over an extended period
of
time. Accordingly, it is difficult to see how such a
train of perceptions
could be an object to which we
could, in an instant, direct our emotions.
I doubt, however, that this is a major
difficulty. Hume himself is aware that
a different
account is needed to deal with those occasions, such
as in
certain emotional states, where we suddenly
come across the object of what
we call
self-awareness. He says, we have noted, that in
order to discover
what is responsible for the
tendency to believe in personal identity, a
distinction must be drawn between "personal
identity, as it regards our
thought or imagination,
and as it regards our passions or the concern we
take in ourselves" (p. 253). Personal identity of
the first sort is his
professed concern in Book I,
while in Book II it is the latter sort. The problem
is that Hume never explains just how we are to
understand the relation between
the two sorts of
personal identity. He obviously wants the personal
identity
that concerns the passions to be basically
the same as that which the imagination
constructs.
This is evident from the descriptions of the self
given in
his discussions of the passions. And yet
his theory seems to require that
the object of the
passions be capable of appearing to awareness in a
way
that does not render it a succession.
The way for us to deal with this problem, and so
fill out our picture of the
no-self theory, is to
see that when we enter a psychological or emotional
state that seems to depend on an instantaneous
awareness of self, what we
are doing is not
reflecting on a succession of related ideas (which
could
not be done at any one instant); rather we are
latching on to a particular
collection of some of
these ideas which, by virtue of their
P.191
being related,
can instantaneously present
themselves in a condensed form to our awareness.
It
is with this discovery of a constructed or condensed
self-image, as
we shall call it, that we are brought
to a central point within the no-self
theory,
namely, that although we may on various occasions
have experiences
of something that we take to be
ourself, on closer examination this object
of our
awareness turns out to be nothing more than a
collation of related
images.
Even some
nonreductionists, such as John
McTaggart, for example, Seem to be alive to
the
possibility that the establishment of what we call
self-perception
would not be enough to prove that a
self exists, but only that something is
perceived as
being a self.(17) This suspicion that we might perceive
something
which we mistakenly believe to be ourself
is borne out by an examination of
our states of
self-awareness. We can start by noting that although
we
do experience occasions of self-awareness, there
are numerous instances in
which it is plain that we
have no awareness of anything that can be considered
a self. Take, for example, my awareness in the
activity of listening to music.
It is often the case
in listening to music that one can become immersed
in the music to the point that there is no room in
consciousness for the awareness
of an I. Here there
is just the experience of the music: the gradual
unfolding
of the melody or theme. And listening to
music is hardly an exceptional case.
Other
activities, such as reading or writing, playing
chess, daydreaming,
and making love, all provide
instances in which one can go on being thoroughly
unaware of oneself. It is, of course, possible for
me to shift my awareness
to a point where I am aware
that I am listening to music, but then I am no
longer immersed in the music. It is important to
see, however, that when I
am thus not immersed, then
my experience of the activity is drastically
altered. This is because, in entering a state of
self-awareness, I undergo
a "giving-up" or a
"forsaking" of the activity in which
I was
previously engaged. My listening gets left behind as
I conjure up
the I to which I now direct my
attention. Here the act of listening loses
its sense
of spontaneity; it becomes something I must struggle
with, something
impeded by the new awareness that it
is I who am doing the listening. The
act of
self-awareness is thus a reflective and complicated
act which involves
both a stepping back from the
flow of experience and the introduction of a
further
element (or rather collation of elements) into that
experience.
It is in this sense, then, that
self-awareness can be called a secondary phenomenon,
for the object of self-awareness is not part of the
basic fabric of experience;
rather it is something
which experience itself fabricates and then takes as
its object. It is, consequently, understandable that
self-awareness, with
its complicated and reflective
qualities, is but an infrequent visitor to
consciousness.
This
view of the secondariness of self-awareness
is supported, I think, by what
we know about the
ontogeny of consciousness. The develop-
P.192
mental psychologist
Jerome Kagan, for example,
delineates a sequence of four psychological
functions which lead up to but do not imply the
emergence of self-awareness.
According to Kagan, the
first function to appear which comes close to
implying the existence of consciousness is
recognition memory. This makes
its appearance in the
first eight months of life and is displayed in the
ability to discriminate between familiar and novel
stimuli. A few months later
there appear the
functions of retrieval and inference, by which Kagan
means "the retrieval of schemata without any cues in
the immediate field
and the generation of inferences
following the relating of those schemata
to present
experience."(18) These functions are demonstrated by
a
child who looks persistently for a toy it just saw
hidden a moment earlier.
Here the child maintains a
schemata of the hiding of the toy and infers that
the toy must still exist somewhere. The fourth
function, which emerges at
about sixteen months,
constitutes the child's ability to monitor, select,
and control the other functions. This function is
the awareness of one's potentiality
for action and,
for Kagan, comes closest to our notion of
consciousness.
The difficulty, however, appears with the
emergence of the fifth function,
namely, the
awareness of self as an entity with characteristics.
This
is a difficulty because, although the function
of self-awareness seems to
depend on the appearance
of the earlier functions, nothing in the earlier
functions implies that self-awareness need emerge:
"To explain why a
30-month-old declares, laughingly,
'I'm a baby,' as she crawls on the floor
and sucks
on a bottle, requires more than an awareness of
one's ability
to act. This behaviour presupposes not
only a schema for one's actions but
also a schema
for the self as an object with variations in
attribute."(19)
Consequently, says Kagan, some new
processes must be introduced into the developmental
sequence if the self-awareness function is to make
its entrance. But just
what this must involve Kagan
cannot say; it remains, we are told, part of
an
ancient enigma.
However, it is not too difficult to see that an
answer to this "enigma"
is already contained within
the account. We need only observe that Kagan's
schema for the self as an object with variations is
just what we have called
the constructed self-image.
That is, it is a collation of earlier experiences
which presents itself in a condensed form to our
awareness. Once we spell
out the schema for the self
in this way we can see that the process needed
to
generate it is not altogether dissimilar to the
process which generates
the fourth function, that
is, the awareness of the potentiality for action.
The child arrives at its action schema by directing
its awareness toward its
own abilities, that is, by
monitoring, selecting, and controlling the more
primitive functions of recognition memory,
retrieval, and inference. Once
the child has
acquired the capacity thus to direct its awareness,
it is
but a small step then to turn this awareness
toward some of the perceptions
which constitute the
succession of related ideas
P.193
and so arrive
at a schema for the self. However,
although the self schema will contain components
not
to be found in other schemata, the components of
other schemata will
nevertheless be discoverable
within the self schema. This is what kagan means,
I
take it, by saying that the function of
self-awareness depends on the
earlier functions.
Thus the infant's awareness of being a baby will
require
more than an awareness of the ability to
act, but will still involve such
an awareness. This
is because to have the awareness "I'm a baby"
is,
among other things, to be aware that one acts like a
baby; and even
a thirty-month old will know that
crawling on the floor and sucking on a bottle
are
things that are (normally) only done by babies. The
reason, however,
why self-awareness will include
more than the child's awareness of its ability
to
act is that, in addition to acting, the child also
is acted upon by
others, has an idea of its own
appearance, experiences emotions, and so on--all
of
which are condensed into the object of
self-awareness. Thus, self-awareness
is a secondary
phenomenon on the ontogenetic theory because it does
not
involve the acquisition of a new ability: it is
merely the deployment of an
earlier function upon a
wider range of objects.
Having established that self-awareness is both a
complicated and rare occurrence,
we can now move on
to the phenomenology of the constructed self-image.
For in laying bare its structure we will see that
although it is the object
of what we call
self-awareness, it is constituted by nothing more
than
a collection of transient images.
One of the central features of the constructed
self-image is that it is a
condensation of related
experiences. It is this feature that helps it to
masquerade as being a self; for, being a
condensation of our experience, it
appears both as a
singular thing (although, as we shall see, this need
not be so) and, at the same time, as something which
contains our experiences.
Since the experiences of
which it is composed may be taken from the different
times of our life, we can also see how the
constructed self-image might, in
an instant, convey
something of the notion of identity over time; that
is, present itself as something that has persisted
throughout our lives.
The psychological process of condensing several
experiences into a single
image or idea is not
unique to the structure of self-awareness. On the
contrary, it is a process commonplace in much of our
psychology. Thus, when
I call up an image of my
friend Mary, I am not presented with a single
portrait, as it were, of Mary. What I find is
several different images of
Mary which have been
collated and superimposed upon one another. I may,
for example, have an image of her hair in the wind,
which at the same time
incorporates the movement of
her dress. This composition may be further blended
with an image of her face which is at once a frontal
view and a profile, and
this in turn may allow the
blueness of her eyes to merge with the turquoise
of
her earrings. In the same instant this
P.194
will all be
bathed in emotional qualities that will
reveal the feelings I have for Mary.
Such images
are, of course, transient, with certain of their
parts being
introduced, expelled, and replaced in an
instant. However, as long as I dwell
on the image of
Mary, there will continue to be an indistinct
network
of constituent images, the older of which
are forever dying away while new
relations take
their place. A similar process of condensation also
seems
to take place in the construction of dream
images, and here, because of what
Freud has called
primary process or the unrestrained character of
hypnagogic
cognition, the resultant complex may
incorporate numerous diverse elements
that are held
together by only the remotest of connections.(20) We
may,
for example, encounter someone in our dreams
who displays the characteristics
of several
different people at once: in one way he is our
childhood playmate,
in another way he is our old
schoolteacher, while in yet a third way he is
someone whom we saw only yesterday. It is as if we
were looking at one of
those anatomy textbooks which
depicts the different organ systems on a series
of
overlapping transparent pages. On the bottom page is
the skeletal system,
on the next page is the nervous
system, and then comes the circulatory system,
and
so on. The end result is a single image of the human
body in which
the different organ systems are
nevertheless discernable.
The constructed self-image is put together in
much the same way as other condensed
images. When I
enter a state of self-awareness, the I that is
summoned
before my consciousness is not a simple
entity that infixes itself changelessly
in my mind.
It is rather a composite of various fading images
which will
have some reference to how I see and feel
about myself. I may, for example,
have an image of
my face as it appeared to me in the mirror this
morning
which is nevertheless infused with features
of previous images of my face.
Thus, although my
eyes and lips might appear to me as they did today,
my cheeks and the shape of my face might seem more
like those of myself of
twelve years ago. Or again
it might include features of how I would imagine
myself to look in twenty years. This composite image
of my face might itself
be superimposed on some
familiar scene, say, the beach where I often go for
walks. Here the sand dunes might be incorporated
into the cheeks and the rising
of the waves into the
forming of a smile. And all of this will be
presented
in a suffusion of affective tones which
will exhibit the emotional evaluations
I have of
myself. Like other of our condensed images, the
self-image will
have but an ephemeral existence; the
constituent images, continuously dissolving
as new
associations, make their way into the complex. Just
what the constituents
of the constructed self-image
are will naturally be different for each person,
since each person will see herself in a different
way. While for one person
it may consist mainly of
idealized images of her physical appearance, for
another it may be a mixture of certain sensations or
emotions, while for a
third it may be
P.195
images of
how others respond to her. To verify that
this is so one need only ask different
persons to
describe what it is they are aware of when they are
aware of
themselves. It will then be seen that such
images vary quite markedly. Further,
it also seems
to be that although some people have a relatively
consistent
image of themselves over time (they have
always seen themselves as a whirling
complex of
emotions), others do not (they now see themselves as
more of
a physical entity than they did five years
ago).
I said above that the constructed self-image
need not exist as a singular
thing; that is, at any
one moment it is possible for a person to have more
than one constructed self-image. And this much seems
to foflow both from what
has been said about the
possible inconsistencies in the self-image over
time, and from the nature of the psychological
mechanism of condensation.
For, in the first place,
if one can construct two or more different images
of
oneself at different times, then the stage is set
for the possibility
of constructing as many
different self-images at the same time. It might be
objected that consciousness could not operate in
this divided way, but various
other phenomena, such
as the findings of research on brain bisection, give
us sufficient grounds to question such an
assumption.(21)
Further, because the constructed self-image is a
condensation of related ideas,
it seems likely that
certain of our ideas which normally appear when we
think of ourselves are such that they bear little
relation to other ideas
that also appear in the same
instant. Consequently, any attempt at condensing
these ideas into a composite idea will tend to fail.
Now in most cases the
solution to this dilemma will
be somehow to repress one of the inconsistent
experiences or at least deny it entry into the
constructed self-image, that
is, not allow it to be
an element in the state of self-awareness. The
problem, however, is that some of these offending
experiences may present
themselves as too salient or
meaningful to accept banishment from the self-image.
What we have, then, is an experience or group of
experiences that is at once
pulled into and yet
expelled from the self-image. Under these conditions
it is quite conceivable that the exiled experiences
might set up their own
camp in which they, too,
could fly the flag of the self-image. There would
then exist two or more groupings of experience, each
of which would present
itself as the appropriate
object of self-awareness. To enter a state of
self-awareness in these circumstances would be to
have one's awareness divide
itself between two
objects competing for the same phenomenological
status.
In understanding how this could occur in
consciousness we must not think of
the constructed
self-image as an object to which I direct my
attention
in the same way that I might direct a beam
of light upon a plane in the sky.
For if we use this
analogy we will be tempted to see the constructed
self-image
and my consciousness of it as if they
were
P.196
two separate entities, the latter of which somehow
engulfs the former. We
will then imagine that to have
two or more simultaneous self-images will involve
little more than having one instant of consciousness
which simultaneously
engulfs more than one thing,
much as one beam of light might illuminate two
planes. But, in reality, the constructed self-image
just is an instant of
consciousness. For when I
enter into a state of self-awareness, what happens
is this: my consciousness throws itself into a
certain configuration that
is structured in the form
of a condensed self-image which permeates or
diffuses over my world at that instant. In this
situation we can begin to
see how parts of my
experience, which are neither assimilable nor
repressible,
might fissure themselves off to become
a separate sphere of consciousness.
A Person in this state might then begin to
experience himself as two distinct
persons.
Something like this could well play a role in the
genesis of
the type of dissociative condition known
as multiple personality. Here the
problem of having
more than one self-image would be dealt with by
producing
a schism in awareness which would
subsequently be attended by the appearance
of two or
more personalities, each of which would be matched
to the appropriate
self-image. I am not saying, of
course, that the constructed sell-image is
to be
identified with the personality, but only that
whatever sort of
image we have of ourselves will
tend to relate both to the way we behave and
to the
way we think, and that, as a consequence, having two
or more radically
distinct self-images will tend to
correlate with having two or more radically
distinct
personalities.
We now have to ask what it is that leads someone
into perceiving the constructed
self-image as being
a self. And here again the work of Buddhist
philosophers
is most helpful. According to Buddhist
theory, what we call a person is really
just an
aggregation of the five khandhas or elements. These
are: physical
form, perceptions, feelings, motives,
and consciousness. But none of these
elements,
whether considered separately or in combination, can
rightly
be identified with the self, for they lack
the various qualities which we
attribute to the
self.(22) This, however, does not stop one from
mistakenly
identifying oneself with one or another
of the elements, and indeed this is
a ubiquitous
confusion from which Buddhism hopes to set us free.
But what
is it that leads a person to this mistaken
identification? To answer this
we need to refer back
to our previous discussion of the conventional and
ultimate levels of truth. There we saw that although
personal names and personal
pronouns do not at the
ultimate level refer to anything, at the
conventional
level it is quite acceptable to use
such expressions for pragmatic reasons.
Thus the
Buddha uses the language of the self as convenient
designations
without being led astray by them. The
problem is that, unlike the Buddha,
many of us do
get led astray by the expressions we use; that is,
in failing
to notice that we are using language at
the level of convention, we end up
P.197
thinking that
there must be something to which the
words "I" or "self"
refer. And so we turn our gaze
inward (because this is where the self is supposed
to exist) and, coming upon one or another of the
elements, or a collection
of the elements, hasten to
identify it with our self. Buddhism underlines
the
importance that language plays here by making a
didactic use of the
Pali word ahamkara, which can
mean both "the utterance of 'I'" and
"I-make."(23)
That the same word has both meanings helps to
suggest a connection between the two meanings: not
only that the language
of the self leads to the
fabrication of a self but also that a fabricated
self leads to a misconstrual of the language of the
self. Here, then, we see
the cyclical nature of the
trap in which the straying language user is caught.
In uttering "I" one is led to misidentify an element
in one's experiences
as the self. Having affected
this delusory identification, one then goes on
to
make similar utterances firm in the belief that
these utterances ultimately
refer to oneself. For
Buddhism, it is thus that we come to weave the first
threads of an ever-expanding veil of delusion. For
in believing that we have
a sell, we are easily led
to other experiences which depend on this illusory
self. Pride and humility, for example, can only get
their foothold if there
is something which we
perceive to be the self and to which we can relate
the causes of our pride or humility. I cannot be proud
of my successes or
humiliated by my failures unless
I believe there is an I to whom these successes
and
failures belong. This is why, on Buddhist theory,
the giving up of
the belief in the self--which we
must do if we are to be free from delusion--is
also
attended by the cessation of pride, humility,
embarrassment, envy,
and other self-oriented (and
hence delusive) emotions.
The Buddhist method for overcoming the delusion
of self is to engage in meditation,
a practice which
may be described as pure internal analysis or
sustained
inward gazing. Through this technique, the
supposed internal self comes to
be seen for what it
is: a mere collection of transient elements. This
realization loosens the grip of the belief in sell
and so dissolves the constructed
self-image back
into the elements from which it came. In one Pali
text,
the Visuddhimagga Sutta or The Path of
Purificalion, we are told that through
the
contemplation of voidness or, what is the same
thing, not-self, "the
misinterpreting (insisting)
that 'a self exists' is abandoned." This
abandoning
occurs "because it has been clearly seen that there
is
no core of permanence and no core of self."(24)
The insight thus acquired,
the Sutta tells us, is
"the death of formations"; the formation
that we
took for a permanent self dies before our very eyes.
Here at last we are in a position to see how
Hume's idea of personal identity
as it regards the
imagination is related to the notion of the
constructed
self-image, or personal identity as it
regards the passions. When I come to
believe that I
am the same person I was twelve years ago, it is
because
of the smooth and uninterrupted progress of
thought
P.198
that is produced
in my imagination when I reflect on
the succession of related ideas. This
is the
imaginary self which is contemplated over time and
whose identity
is fictitious. When, on the other
hand, I believe that I am perceiving my
self in an
instant of self-awareness, such as when I experience
a self-oriented
emotion, what is happening is that
my awareness is being directed to an object
which is
merely a condensed version of extracts from the
succession of
related ideas. This is the constructed
self-image, which is a rare and secondary
aspect of
consciousness. In either case, what I come upon is
merely a
collection of experiences: in either case,
there is no sell to be found.
NOTES
This essay
is a version of part of a doctoral thesis
which was accepted by the University
of Edinburgh in
1989. I should like, therefore, to thank the
University
of Edinburgh and the Committee of
Vice-Chancellors and Principals of the Universities
and Colleges of the United Kingdom, from both of
whom I received the scholarships
which helped to
make this research possible.
1 - For a discussion of how the bodily version of
reductionism misconstrues
the nature of the
body, see my "Bodily Theory and Theory of the
Body,
" Philosophy 66, no. 257 (July 1991):
339-347.
2 - David Hume, A
Treatise of Human Nature, ed. J.
A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1978),
p. 525. Further references are to this edition
and are indicated
in the text. Unless stated
otherwise, all italics within this and
subsequent
quotes are Hume's.
3 - Terence Penelhum, "Hume on Personal Identity, "
The Philosophical
Review 64 (1955): 571.
4 - James Noxon, "Senses of Identity in Hume's
Treatise, " Dialogue:
Canadian Philosophical
Review 8 (1969): 367-384.
5 - lbid., pp. 372-373.
6 - Penelhum, "Hume," p. 578.
7 - Trans. K. N. Jayatilleke in Early Buddhist
Theory of Knowledge (London:
Alien & Unwin,
1963), p. 319.
8 - Ibid., p. 361.
9 - Trans. Steven Collins in Selfless Persons:
Imagery and Thought in Theravada
Buddhism
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982),
p.154.
P.199
10 - In Sources
of Indian Tradition, ed. Wm.
Theodore de Bary (New York: Columbia University
Press, 1958) , vol. 1, pp. 103-105. The
following translation comes mainly
from this
edition. However, the editor omits the
important final remark
made by Nagasena. This
line, which I have included, can be found in
The
Sacred Books of the Buddhists, vol. 23,
Milinda's Questions, trans. I. B.
Horner
(London. Luzac, 1963), bk. 1, pp. 37-38.
11 - For example, Derek Parfit, in Reasons and
Persons (Oxford: Claredon Press,
1984), p. 273.
Parfit is one of those who fail to distinguish
between
the eliminative no-self theory and
reductionism. Consequently, he mistakenly
thinks that the Buddhist position supports his
reductionism.
12 - Trans. J. P. Stern in Lichtenberg: A Doctrine
of Scattered Occasions
(Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 1959), p. 270.
13 - Stern does not seem to me to be aware of this
point in his discussion
of Lichtenberg. See
ibid., p. 270.
14 - There are also the so-called "second thoughts"
in the Appendix
to the Treatise (pp. 633-636),
where Hume seems to express doubts about the
truth of his account of personal identity.
Here, however, I follow Norman
Kemp Smith in
thinking that the passage in question is in
fact a reaffirmation
of his principles and that
his only doubts are with his theory's ability
to account for states of self-awareness. This,
as will be seen, is not a difficulty
for a more
expanded version of Hume's account. For Kemp
Smith's remarks
on the Appendix, see his The
Philosophy of David Hume: A Critical Study of
its Origins and Central Doctrines (London:
Macmillan, 1931), pp. 553-560.
15 - Kemp Smith, The Philosophy of David Hume, p.
171.
16 - Ibid., p. vi.
17 - John McTaggart, The Nature of Existence
(Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press), vol.
2, chap. 36.
18 - Jerome Kagan, The Second Year: The Emergence of
Self-Awareness (Cambridge,
Massachussetts:
Harvard University Press, 1981), pp. 148-149.
19 - Ibid., p. 149.
20 - For a discussion of primary process, see
Sigmund Freud, The Standard
Edition of the
Complete Psychological Works vol. 5, The
Interpretation
of Dreams, ed. J. Strachey
(London: Hogarth Press, 1964), pp. 599-609.
21 - See Thomas Nagel's "Brain Bisection and the
Unity of Consciousness,"
in Personal identity,
ed. John Ferry (Berkeley: University of
California
Press, 1975).
P.200
22 - For the Dialogue in which this argument is
given, see The Collection
of the Middle-Length
Savings (Majjhima Nikaya), trans. I. B. Horner
(London:
Pali Text Society, 1957), vol. 1, sec.
233.
23 - See J.A.B. van Buitenen, "Studies in Samkhaya
II," Journal
of the American Oriental Society
77 (1957): 15-25.
24 - Buddhaghosa, The Path of Purification
(Visuddhimagga) , 2d ed., trans.
Bhikkhu
Nyanamoli (Columbo: A. Semage, 1964), p. 815.