Of the many philosophical developments from the Buddha's
viewpoint, possibly the most in line with the Buddha's traditional silence about
philosophical questions was that of the Madhyamika school, as voiced by the
philosopher Nagarjuna. It is unlikely that any philosophical exploration of
ontological and epistemological issues would have especially reflected the Buddha's
original intent, but of the many philosophical detailings that ultimately came
out of his tradition, the exploration of Nagarjuna would probably have displeased
him the least. This is because Nagarjuna's intent was to answer the questions
to which the Buddha only responded with silence, and because Nagarjuna's answer
was arguably very close to the same thing--shunyata. Where other Buddhists proposed
existent mind or matter, Nagarjuna proposed nothing as independently existing.
Everything was dependently originating. Nagarjuna's most important argument
was his philosophical dialectic, the result of which, he maintained, was the
conventional proof that no philosophical explanation of reality was ultimate.
Unfortunately for Nagarjuna, his proof may not have been as complete as he thought--he
may be saying more in espousing shunyata than his dialectic is able to prove.
Nagarjuna is taken to be the voice of the Madhyamika school (Koller 196). Unlike
other Buddhist thinkers, he did not abandon philosophical enquiry altogether.
Instead, he used a philosophical examination to show how common ideas of permanence
and causality, upon which our conventional ideas about the universe are based,
are inadequate or self-contradictory. Nagarjuna's primary argument was against
causality. He argued that the concept of causality ultimately contradicts itself.
Nagarjuna asserted that there were only four possible relationships that an
effect can have with its cause. Either it is caused by itself alone, by something
other than itself, by itself and some other thing, or by neither itself nor
another. This is merely a detail of the possibilities for causal connections.
Nagarjuna argued: If a thing was caused by itself and nothing else, then no
change has occurred and nothing has been caused. If a thing is caused by something
other than itself, then something has been produced from nothing. If a thing
is caused both by itself and by some other thing, then in the extent to which
it is self-similar, there is no change or causation, and in the extent to which
it is caused by something else, something has come from nothing, which cannot
be. Finally, if a thing is caused by neither itself nor anything else, it has
not been caused, because there is no cause. Thus, Nagarjuna argues, nothing
can be caused by another thing.
Another important argument that is yielded by Nagarjuna's dialectical method
is against ordinary notions of time. He argues that if present and future depend
on the past, as we believe, that they would have to exist in the past. But they
do not. If they do not exist in the past, they must not be dependant on the
past. If they are not dependant on the past, what can they be dependant on?
Thus, Nagarjuna concludes, time must have no concrete reality and can only make
sense in reference to other dependently originating things. Taken together,
these arguments go a long way toward supporting Nagarjuna's idea that conventional
ideas about reality are inadequate. They go a long way to suggest that the ultimate
nature of reality may be shunyata, or emptiness.
There are a number of traditional responses to Nagarjuna's dialectic. One claims
that Nagarjuna's version of reality is nihilistic--because there is no ultimately
existent reality. Nagarjuna escapes this criticism by pointing out that his
dialectic contains no propositions, it only shows how conventional propositions
contradict one another. He also says of shunyata that it is only empty insofar
as it is impossible to categorize using conventional notions. Indeed, Nagarjuna
splits reality into two truths--conventional truths which we live with and entertain,
and ultimate truth, which is not describable in words and can only be called
shunyata. Other critics claim that his view is self-critical--that if shunyata
cannot be described in conventional terms, then his dialectic and his distinction
between conventional and ultimate truth are conventional and so cannot reflect
ultimate reality. Nagarjuna counters by claiming that though conventional truth
is not ultimately true, it can point to ultimate truth, which his philosophy
does.
Nagarjuna's ultimate purpose was similar to the Buddha's--he intended to show
that philosophical notions are inadequate to describe ultimate reality, that
it must be experienced. Unlike other Buddhists who shunned philosophical approaches,
Nagarjuna thought that it would be helpful to come to a philosophical understanding
of the problem of philosophy on the way to experiencing ultimate reality directly.
But did Nagarjuna succeed in proving that ultimate reality is shunyata? Is there
a clear connection between his negative argument and his positive assertions?
I submit that there is not. Nagarjuna's negative argument is strong and clear.
He proves with great adeptness that conventional notions of time and causality
are less than ultimately coherent. He admits that they serve conventional purposes
well and sets up a scheme for talking about causal relationships as characterized
by conditions rather than causes. But does it follow from the inadequacy of
current conventional notions that any conventional notion would be inadequate?
This is definitely unclear.
If we consider current notions of time (t1) and causality (c1) as two of a set
D of possible descriptions of reality, such that D contains descriptions t1,
c1, t2, c2... tn, cn, then what Nagarjuna succeeds in proving using his dialectic
is not-t1 and not-c1. Since Nagarjuna's negative argument is strong, we accept
not-t1 and not-c1. But Nagarjuna's positive argument, that the ultimate reality
cannot be described in conventional terms has a different flavor than merely
not-t1 and not-c1. Nagarjuna's positive argument is more of the sort not-D,
that no conventional description of reality can reflect ultimate reality accurately,
that shunyata is called empty precisely because it is uncategorizable in conventional
terms. Nagarjuna is attempting to employ the Law of the Excluded Middle, but
the situation is far too complex to admit such a polarized distinction (Murti
146). Nagarjuna seeks to exclude all possible explanations by excluding the
ordinary ones, and in this respect his argument fails to be adequate. Granted,
he will functionally exclude most or all of the ordinary notions that we entertain,
ideas of time and causality being as central as they are to our ways of thinking.
But it is important to note that just because we have no concepts of reality
which do not fail to include ideas of time or causality, does not mean they
cannot exist. Nagarjuna's argument needs either a proof that the set of possible
descriptions D can only contain t1 and c1, or a list of all other possible t
and c, why they are the only possible t and c, and how they are inadequate.
Nagarjuna's denial of time and causality primarily denies the possibility of
change for independently existing objects. Thus it denies the appropriateness
of our concepts of time and causality. What it fails to deny (and indeed Nagarjuna
would probably espouse) is the idea of a connectedness between objects or events
that we ordinarily think of as being causally related. If our intuition of connectedness
is correct, then the conventional conceptual framework need not be denied the
status of ultimacy on the sole basis of inadequate notions of time and causality.
Ultimately, what Nagarjuna succeeds in proving is that our notions of time and
causality are inadequate, so if we can correct, replace, or remove these faulty
notions from our conventional understanding, it may not be subject to Nagarjuna's
criticisms.
For example, we may consider causality as a number of discrete conceptual components
working together: time, change, and connectedness. The concept of time involves
a reality that exists moment to moment, with an existent present moment a no-longer-existent
past moment, and a yet-to-exist future moment. The idea of change involves independent
objects which once were, now are, and will be but are not yet. Note that change
and time are almost inextricably bound (not as discrete as we would like)--general
concepts of past and future involve a change of the present moment, and require
a change of present objects to be detectable. Connectedness, on the other hand,
is altogether a different sort of concept than either time or change, and requires
connections to neither. Thus it may not be fallible to the same arguments. In
fact, we avow the continuity of spatial relationships, both within and without
objects, as a kind of connectedness not subject to time or change. That is,
we ordinarily think of one slice of desk, mountain, or air as being connected
to the next by virtue or its proximity, and we are not required to compare one
moment to the next or establish a causal relationship for the connection to
be plausible. It just is. We just think of space as a continuous continuum.
If we take the concept of causality, then, and remove from it the notions of
time as coming-to-be and ceasing-to-be, cut out the notion of change entirely,
and come to view it in the same way we ordinarily view space, we avoid entirely
the notions of time and causality that Nagarjuna proved faulty. Our universe,
then, would become a four-dimensional solid in which no change occurs. (Human
consciousness should not be a problem for this so long as it is viewed as completely
material and as such completely determined).
And this alternative notion of time has important implications for many of negative
Buddhist arguments which shore up notions of dependant origination or shunyata.
The argument against permanence, for instance, is undermined because the universe
would be static. The concept is not perfect, it conflicts with ordinary notions
of humans, for instance, but that may only mean that our ordinary notions of
humans are inadequate. Despite the obviously unsavory implications and possible
problems of such an alternative conception of time and causality (the impossibility
of human freedom, for instance), it illustrates an important point--that there
are other possible members of the set D (other ways to ground our conceptual
framework than traditional notions of time and causality) whose possibility
Nagarjuna has failed to deny or whose inadequacy Nagarjuna has failed to show.
Nagarjuna was attempting to answer the philosophical questions--the questions
to which the Buddha remained silent. He thought that he could help people to
realize the ultimate nature of reality by showing how conventional truths fail
to be ultimately true. He attempted to do this by showing, through his dialectic,
that since conventional notions are contradictory the nature of the ultimate
reality must be uncategorizable--shunyata. Unfortunately, because current conceptions
of causality are not the only possible conceptions of causality, Nagarjuna's
argument is missing one of two important steps. For his argument to be convincing,
he must either prove that the set D of possible conceptions of reality can only
include current notions of time and space, or he must list the other possible
notions of time and space and show how they are inadequate. Note that the possibility
of other conceptions of time or causality is insufficient to disprove Nagarjuna's
positive argument. The ultimate nature of reality may well be shunyata, and
conventional notions of reality may truly lack the potential to do more than
point at reality. Even so, the necessity for a connection between his positive
and negative arguments remains. In the end, it seems that philosophical undertakings
demand a rigor that the Buddha's silence did not. Perhaps, if enlightenment
is possible without tackling philosophy on its home field, then the Buddha's
response was the more prudent, if not the more convincing.
Bibliography
Koller, John M. Oriental Philosophies. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice
Hall.1985.
Murti. T. R. V. The Central Philosophy of Buddhism: A Study of the Madhyamika
System. London: Ruskin House. 1960.
Jha, Ram Chandra. The Vedantic and the Buddhist Concept of Reality as Interpreted
by Samkara and Nagarjuna. Calcutta: Print O Print. 1973.