Abstract
Cognitivism,
presently the major paradigm of psychology, presents a scientific account of mental
life. Buddhism also presents an account of mental life, but one which is integral
with its wider ethical and transcendental concerns. The postmodern appraisal of
science provides a framework within which these two accounts may be compared without
inheriting many of the assumed oppositions between science and religion.
It
is concluded that cognitivism and Buddhism will have complementary roles in the
development of a more pluralist psychological science. In this development it
will be necessary to address what are the values that are implicit in science.
Introduction
Buddhism
qua religion, and psychology qua science might be expected to have little in common.
Religion is framed as assertions of transcendental truth and depends for its authority
on shared faith in revelation. It is thus and to that extent absolute and final.
Science on the other hand is framed as theories of material truth whose authority
rests in the degree to which they can withstand disproof. It is thus and to that
extent relative and provisional. Science deals in public and explicit facts while
religion deals with private and tacit beliefs. While science is taken to be value-neutral
natural philosophy, religion transmits and re-casts a system of values. Accordingly,
while religion can be relatively unconcerned about the mundane world, science,
secure in its unique authority, takes no more account of religion than of any
other system of culturally relative myth. It seems, then, that any significant
interaction between the two is unlikely.
In the postmodern era, this caricature
of the modernist divide between science and religion has far less force. A shift
is taking place towards a more pluralist arena within which due weight is given
to other cultural discourses which recognize the subjectivity of the human condition
as well as objectivist science. Such a move, at the turn of the present century,
echos the pluralist stance of William James who, at the turn of the last, found
no difficulty in pursuing psychology as the Science of Mental Life while at the
same time addressing the Varieties of Religious Experience.
There are at least
two reasons why the assumed opposition of science and religion can be set aside
when Buddhism and scientific psychology are considered. First, Buddhism is not
a religion in the same sense as the Abrahamic religions to which the modernist
division of science and religion applies most directly. It is especially inappropriate
to identify Buddhism with faith, revelation, an immortal soul and a personified
Creator. There is neither a Creator, nor soul in Buddhism and inasmuch as anything
like faith or revelation is concerned, it is the confidence that certain teachings
provide the means to know important facts of human existence. Since these teachings
must be personally explored and tested, Buddhism is also a practice, an empirical
mental culture which has been developed by systematic investigation rather than
fixed by faith in revelation. It is in this sense that Buddhist and scientific
psychology can be placed in relation and compared.
Second, psychology is not
a science. Not, that is, in the modern positivist sense, because of the essential
subjectivity of its central phenomenon, consciousness. Despite the enigmas of
contemporary physics, modernist science continues to assume that its subject matter
is independent of the human mind. It is this that makes it possible to believe
that a positivist program can be pursued. Of course, the mind can be treated as
if it were a material object. Indeed, most psychological studies of perception,
memory are, in general, objective in the conventional positivist sense, and for
most of its history psychology has marginalised phenomenology as part of a positivist
program.
But this is to study the vehicle of mental life rather than the thing
itself. To deal with the mind appropriately means that psychology needs to be
fundamentally rather than incidentally concerned with consciousness. But consciousness,
the principal and unique justification for the existence of psychology itself,
is essentially a phenomenological matter, which means that it cannot stand as
a science in the modernist, positive sense. If psychology abandons consciousness
then it will be crucially incomplete. If it does not, then it perforce becomes
a special case within positive science.
Scientific psychology presently takes
cognitivism as its principal paradigm, replacing the behaviourism that dominated
the discipline up to the late 1950's. In what follows, 'cognitivism' will be used
as a collective term for what are variously refered to as, the information processing
approach, functionalism, cognitive psychology, cognitive science, the cognitive
approach and a variety of of other related terms. Cognitivism seeks a unified,
formal theory of the rational component of psychological functions such as language,
perception, memory and thought. The principal means to develop this formal theory
is to describe the operation of the brain in computational terms. This is not
just a metaphor. The brain is not studied "as if" it were carrying out
some sort of computation. Instead, it is assumed that what the brain does can
be formalised in terms of computational theory.
It is this effort after a unified
formal theory that shows the degree to which cognitivism inherits the positivist
program of modernist science. The effort is to perfect, through a program of theory
development, computer simulation and empirical investigation, a unified, formal
and mechanistic account of a particular level of mental life, that is, of rational
cognitive processing. Once developed, this account will help to understand how
other aspects of mental life, including intentionality, the emotions and subjectivity,
are produced and supported by this level. This program has been very productive
during the second half of this century and presently cognitivism exerts a great
influence over most of psychology and over related disciplines.
Happily, unlike
behaviourism, cognitivism does not reject consciousness. This, over the past decade
or so, has made its way back towards the top of the psychological agenda. It would
thus seem an appropriate time to consider the interaction that might be possible
with Buddhism, where consciousness has been the focus of investigation for some
twenty five centuries. We shall start by identifying some Buddhist sources and
specifying in more detail the aspects of cognitivism with which they might be
compared.
Buddhist texts and cognitivism.
Although Buddhism and cognitivism
are situated within very different cultural and metaphysical frameworks, both
deal with the workings of the mind, the mind body relationship and the nature
of human action. Perhaps most significantly here, both present systematic systems
of psychological enquiry. Accordingly, some attempt to bring the two into relation
can be made so long as there is proper regard for what may and may not be compared.
The
sources that have been used here are mostly early Buddhist texts. The developments
of later periods has not obscured their fundamentally psychological nature. However,
Buddhism addresses the transcendental context of the human condition and cannot
be treated as if it were a Western scientific theory; there is no such thing as
Buddhist psychology apart from Buddhism in toto. The psychological teachings of
Buddhism must also be considered together with the practices of mental culture
within which these teachings are comprehensible. Even so, the psychological content
of early Buddhism is patent and deals with everyday cognitive processes such as
perception, attention and feeling. This is what will here be called Buddhist psychology
and which will be compared to cognitivism.
Buddhism presents, to a very rough
approximation in Western terms, a phenomenological psychology founded on process
metaphysics. Human mental life is portrayed as caught up in samsara, or the cycle
of conditioned and illusory existence. The interplay of physical and mental causes
are set out in the doctrine of dependent origination which describes the arising
and the sustaining of the ego: a centre of awareness, affect, sensation, discriminative
awareness, thinking, volition, action and consciousness. The real nature of samsara
is obscured by ignorance, craving and frustration which distort psychological
processes and lead to actions that, unless skilfully managed, entangle human beings
more deeply in the cycle of conditioned existence. The result is that experience
of the human condition is primarily one of dissatisfaction. The cure is to understand
that the psycho-physical processes underlying the flow of human experience are
not psychological absolutes, but skills that may be improved. Thus the purpose
and character of Buddhist psychology is fundamentally therapeutic. The objective
being to become more skilled in managing human mental life and to promote more
satisfactory living.
Even from such a condensed account, it is clear that Buddhism
presents many sharp contrasts with cognitivsm. While these place limits on integration
between the two, they are no bar to quite detailed comparison. Broadly speaking,
the more productive comparisons have not attempted to assimilate Eastern to Western
views or vice versa but rather to place the two within a more inclusive context.
This
integrative stance is in line with the postmodern appraisal of science in general
and to psychological science in particular. A postmodern, pluralist psychology
can reduce the assumed opposition between cognitivism qua science and Buddhism
qua religion. Instead, it becomes possible to explore their similarities and contrasts
as a mean to creating a more complete and developed science of the mind. Accordingly,
the next section examines some ways in which cognitivism and Buddhism might interact.
Models
of interaction.
Comparing Buddhism with cognitivism may be to make some sort
of category error, in which case no significant interaction is to be expected.
This null case inherits the assumed incompatibility of Buddhism and cognitivism
from the modernist separation of scientific realism from religious transcendentalism.
There is a prima facie case for the null model in, for instance, the clear methodological
contrasts. The methodological stance of cognitivism is public and objective theory
development. Buddhist practices are essentially individualistic, phenomenological
and based on historically grounded teachings. Practices that might be represented
in Buddhism as verification might, from a scientific point of view, be seen as
indoctrination.
Given these and many other differences we could simply conclude
that there can be no significant interaction. This may in time turn out to be
the case, but as a way of proceeding, or not proceeding, it has little to recommend
it. It is becoming clear that many assumed barriers to interaction result from
a projective distortion of Buddhist thought which over-emphasises transcendence
and obscures its empirical content .
The postmodern turn also encourages a
move away from the null model. Recent discussions reveal that cognitivism is an
eclectic arena in which different approaches to the mind may be brought into relation
with one another. More broadly, it is now clear that science is more intimately
embedded within a wider framework of cultural influences than was previously thought.
Science is a type of collective cultural perception, rather than an isolated logical
edifice. More specifically, Whiteheadian organicism is explicitly cited as a more
appropriate philosophical base for a postmodern science. Process metaphysics is
clearly more appropriate to organic sciences like biology and psychology and opens
the door to a more detailed interaction with Buddhism. Partly as a result of these
shifts in the view of science in general and of cognitivism in particular, there
has been a recent upsurge of dialogue between Buddhism and scientists, including
cognitive scientists.
The null model is unproductive and perpetuates the assumed
incompatibility between religious and scientific accounts of the human phenomenon.
This historically imposed difficulty need not hinder more productive models which
assume that significant interaction is possible Once more specific issues are
considered, for example the role of consciousness and the relationship between
cognition and affect, the possibilities for interaction expand.
A more productive
model of interaction might be to take Buddhism and cognitivism as offering complementary
perspectives on the mind. Where one treats the mind as an external object the
other treats it as something to be known through subjective experience; one emphasises
individual investigation while the other adopts the collective consensual style
of modernist science and so on. Complementarity may be appropriate in studies
of meditation and other altered states of consciousness where Buddhism offers
techniques to create altered states of consciousness while the West has technological
means to study them. Here, Buddhism have a rich vocabulary while the West has
powerful means to operationalise that vocabulary.
Jung found in Buddhism a
significant complement to those elements of psychoanalysis, religion and science
from which he synthesised his own views and practice. He was, however cautious
on how far this synthesis might go. His view was that the over-rationality of
Western scientism has created a collective psychic need for the mystical and transcendental
elements supposed to be the essential characteristic of Buddhism. This makes it
difficult for Buddhism to be appraised in the West without projective distortion.
Thus Jung, while supporting the comparison of psychoanalysis and Zen, suggested
that such work would be limited by deeply rooted differences in the cultural and
psycho-historical contexts of the two subjects.
Another alternative to the
null model is to propose that Buddhism and cognitivism will be found to resemble
each other in some respects, even if theoretical grounds for this will be difficult
to discover. Naturally, some degree of resemblance is to be expected. Equally,
however, since the metaphysical basis and methods of the two systems are so different,
it may not be possible to decide whether this resemblance is superficial or otherwise.
Resemblances are easily identified, but explanations are more difficult to find.
There are, for example, numerous studies of the resemblance between early Buddhist
practices for behaviour change and contemporary Western psychotherapeutic techniques,
especially behaviour therapy. Nonetheless it is unclear just how far this resemblance
can be accounted for theoretically.
Of course, where therapeutic aims are to
be fulfilled, resemblances may be accepted on pragmatic grounds. For instance
, the similarity between Rational Emotive Therapy and therapeutic techniques based
on Buddhist practices are clear, but are simply acknowledged without being analysed
in any detail. Resemblances have also been identified in behaviour modification
and psychoanalysis. It is no accident that these cases concern therapy. The essence
of Buddhist psychology is therapeutic and significant correspondences with Western
psychotherapeutic theory and practice are thus not so surprising, given their
pragmatic character. What is perhaps more surprising is that the basis for these
correspondences is often relatively precise objectives concerning changes in cognitive
function.
However, progress beyond resemblance may be possible in respect of
cognitivism given that it is underpinned by a more explicit theory. Perhaps the
strongest alternative to the null case would be the claim that it is possible
to put Buddhism and cognitivism into precise correspondence, despite apparent
differences. Furthermore, Buddhism has had little or no recourse to physiology
or to relatively technical matters such as information theory or formal linguistics.
Also apart from these obvious differences there are less obvious but not less
significant ones. For example, cognitivist methods are for the empirical development
of a theory. Buddhist practices of mental culture are not for development of a
theory but for its experiential verification and use. Buddhism changes slowly
and, in as much as it transmits fundamental teachings, may even be said not to
change at all. By contrast cognitivism, like any science, changes incessantly.
Buddhism relies heavily on the experiences of exceptionally trained individuals
while cognitivism relies on objective data, often averaged over groups of ordinary
people. Although many studies of Buddhism and Western psychology have appeared
all are cautious about precise correspondence between, say, specific psychological
structures or the timing of mental events.
For the moment, the expectation
of precise correspondence is not realistic. A mixture of resemblance and complementarity
covers the present situation. It may be possible to move closer to a correspondence
position in future. The questions is: how might this move be made? The next section
examines how Buddhism might influence the development of cognitivism.
Buddhism
and the development of cognitivism.
Cognitivism, like any science, is in a
constant state of development. Specific, peripheral issues turn over rapidly while
more general, central topics such as memory, perception and reasoning remain comparatively
stable. Although subject to more measured development, these central topics, along
with a distinctive methodology, maintain cognitivism's persistent identity. The
lively activity of peripheral topics combined with longer term movements of the
central ones gives the development of the whole an amoeba-like character. While
movement of the central issues to some extent generates the activity in more peripheral
ones, the peripheral topics are more reactive to the wider intellectual milieu,
and transmit directive influences back to the centre. These influences include
the image of science on which cognitivism models itself. This image is changing.
The modernist unitary discipline, dominated by reduction and Cartesian mechanism
is giving way to a postmodern pluralist discourse in which reduction is balanced
by emergence and mechanism is tempered with Whiteheadian organicism.
Following
the amoeba analogy, the development of cognitivism can be said to be the resultant
of a complex of internal and external forces or indicator. It thus may be asked
how Buddhism might play a role as either an internal or external indicator. As
an internal indicator Buddhism might, in conjunction with contemporary research,
be involved in the generation and testing of theoretical alternatives. As an external
indicator Buddhism might contribute to the general direction of research and to
the development of a more pluralist methodology. Illustrations of both these roles
can be found.
Buddhism as an internal indicator.
An example of how Buddhism
might act as an internal indicator is provided by the issue concerning the relationship
of cognition and emotion. Until quite recently this question has been regarded
as something that would have to be left until the cognitive bedrock of mental
life had been located. As a recent historian of cognitivism puts it, there has
been: "..... the deliberate decision to de-emphasise certain factors which....would
unnecessarily complicate the cognitive scientific enterprise. These include the
influence of emotions ....".
Cognitivism marginalises emotion as one of
a number of factors that are somehow outside of cognition proper, that is, not
necessary parts of it but rather optional adjuncts to it To consider these factors
at the same time would be to obscure the rational foundations of cognition. Implicit
in this approach is an ordering of objectives. First some understanding of basic
cognitive mechanisms must be achieved; this is why a formal computational theory
has been one of cognitivism's major objectives. After this, it is assumed, it
will be possible to show how these mechanisms underpin other aspects of mental
life, including, eventually, awareness and feelings. It is not that emotion is
irrelevant, nor that it is a false category of mental life, rather it is that
emotion is taken to be necessarily subsequent to basic cognitive mechanisms such
as recognition, memory and judgement and these, therefore, must be understood
first. The phenomenological world and its emotional accompaniment must wait its
turn.
Cognitivism's treatment of emotion is predominantly concerned with its
rational precursors and how it functions as an adjunct to processes such as attention,
decision making or memory. A clear position on this issue is taken by Lazarus
who suggests that cognitive interpretation necessarily and always involved in
emotional responses and that, as he puts it, 'cognitive appraisal (of meaning
or significance) underlies and is an integral feature of all emotional states.'
However,
a number of objections have been raised against this view, from the very earliest
periods of modern psychology and in more recent times, both from within cognitivism
specifically and also from other perspectives, such as psychoanalytic theories
of development. Even those taking a cognitivist line occasionally consider emotion
as a deus ex machina to be invoked when pure rationality runs into difficulties.
For example, the problem cognitivism has in accounting, mechanistically, for the
ceteris paribus reasoning that is the hallmark of natural intelligence has led
to the suggestion that emotions are involved in selecting between competing objects
of attention or lines of inference. Likewise, cognitivists who have considered
creative thought, often recognise that it is guided more by emotions and aesthetics
than by reason and logic. Here, emotion is necessarily bound up in cognitive processes
as they occur, not as something that emerges as a post hoc by-product. Thus, in
sharp distinction to the position of Lazarus, Zajonc offers substantial support
for the view that cognition is not the necessary precursor to all emotional reactions.
These
positions on the relationship between emotion and cognition are clear and distinct.
On the one hand emotion is taken to be involved in cognitive processes in such
a way that cognitive evaluation is taken to be a necessary precondition for emotional
experience. On the other, questions of order or precedence have relatively little
meaning. Buddhism has a discriminative position on this issue, but before turning
to it, is first worth considering another theoretical dichotomy, this time concerning
conscious awareness.
Mandler contrasts two positions on the cognitive determinants
of conscious experience. One, which he labels the identity view, takes consciousness
to be an unprocessed reflection of autonomous cognitive operations. This position
derives from theories which identify conscious experience with the input to the
currently most dominant of a large number of independent, competing cognitive
subsystems. This suggests that consciousness is post hoc, and that the workings
of cognitive mechanisms autonomously determine the phenomenological flow. This
recalls Thomas Huxley's comment that consciousness was as causally significant
to the workings of the mind as the steam-whistle was to the progress of a steam
locomotive. Such views of conscious experience portray it bobbing in the wake
of self-determining cognitive mechanisms.
By contrast, a second view, which
Mandler labels the constructivist position, presents consciousness itself as the
autonomous element and the origin of freely chosen adaptive action. Under this
view, most conscious states ".....are constructed out of ... preconscious
structures in response to the requirements of the moment ... phenomenal experience
is a construction ... " that is, a form of narration under personal control.
This view takes consciousness to be part of human agency which composes other
cognitive products into a phenomenological flow according to need. This is more
in line with what folk psychology takes consciousness to be, the point of emergence
of a flow of autonomous, self-directed action.
Of course, autonomy is a difficult
matter. Consciousness, like cognition in general, is context bound both in the
immediate sense of the internal and external conditions supporting it and in the
longer term sense of the cultural patterns which influence it. Thus, while the
contents of awareness may be autonomous to some extent, they nonetheless necessarily
reflect the possibilities for action afforded by perceptual input, as has been
emphasised by phenomenological psychology.
We now have two illustrations where
Buddhism may help to decide between theoretical alternatives. In the first case,
the question is whether cognition is emotion's only begetter or whether, following
Pascal, we accept that emotion can have equally important precognitive roots.
In the second case the question is whether conscious experience is a passive record
of prior cognitive events or whether it is a form of narrative whose moment to
moment structure is subject to tacit needs and socio-cultural beliefs.
With
respect to the first case, Buddhism holds that although cognitive evaluation and
recognition are precursors to emotion in certain cases, it is also clear that
in a more significant sense, emotion is taken to be precognitive. Buddhist sources
emphasise that emotion is a necessary accompaniment to all stages of the mind's
workings. More importantly again, is the first result of sensory contact with
the world. The emotional tone of all sensory and mental experience is the motor
of mental life and the flow of human experience. The first consequence of sensory
contact is said not to be sensation, recognition or awareness or any other cognitive
activity but an emotional reaction. This supports a view of emotion as implicit
any psychological process; emotion and cognition are necessarily interlinked.
This casts doubt on the marginalisation of emotion on grounds of methodological
hygiene. Emotion is primary, not secondary; as Langer claims: "Feeling ....
is the mark of mentality". Donaldson too, in discussing the limitations of
cognitivism's treatment of emotion, argues for more attention to Buddhist views.
Turning
to the second case, it is clear that Buddhism draws something like the distinction
between the identity and constructivist positions on consciousness While biophysical
activity is recognised as necessary enabling condition for mental experience,
a fundamental Buddhist principle of is that conscious awareness is structured
according to values, views and needs, much as the constructivist position maintains.
Indeed, since the flow of conscious experienced is thus liable to be distorted
by craving and attachment this can become a source of error and suffering. Buddhist
practice aims to free consciousness from these distorting influences so that,
as the following quotation from the Suttas states: "In the seen there will
just be the seen, in the heard, just the heard; in the sensed, just the sensed
and in the cognised, just the cognised."
Buddhist teaching and practice
have as their aim the more skilled management of consciousness and a lessening
of emotionally distorted reactions to promote psychological insight and growth.
In line with the constructivist position, Buddhist psychology implies that rather
than being a passive record of cognitive mechanisms, the contents of consciousness
are actively fashioned. Conscious experience is a construct not a trace.
To
summarise, Buddhism promotes the image of emotion as a parallel accompaniment
to cognition rather than a product of cognitive discrimination. It also promotes
the image of consciousness as the active component in the construction of mental
states and not the passive, post hoc trace of autonomous mental mechanisms. Thus
we have two illustrations of Buddhism having a position on theoretical alternatives
within cognitivism, that is, acting as an internal indicator.
Buddhism as an
external indicator.
Given the postmodern context in which psychology will develop,
Buddhism may also act as an external indicator in a number of ways. One example
is the rebalancing between reductionism and holism. Cognitivism, following the
model of positivist science, generally favours the former. Complex mental effects
are to be understood by reduction to simpler causes such as neurological or information
processing mechanisms. The reason being that were the mind to be addressed from
the holist perspective, its component parts would be obscured. Only a thorough
knowledge of these supposed components will do for a proper science of the mind;
adopting cognitivism as the unified theory of psychology will avoid the discipline
degenerating into mere relativistic phenomena collection.
But reductionism
has consequences. Not only are cognitive processes to be decomposed, hampering
proper phenomenological engagement with them but also cognition must be isolated
from other aspects of mental life such as affect and volition. Such an approach
is only justifiable if it is accepted that cognitivism model itself on those sciences
where analytic reductionism has proved effective. But, as is proposed here, the
subject matter of psychology is unique in a way that rules out taking other sciences
as a model in this way. Therefore, this justification for analytic reductionism
fails.
Following the postmodern turn, a more even balance is being sought between
reduction and holism, particularly in the biological sciences. Reduction on its
own cannot disclose the nature of organic systems, and it is clear that the mind
is intimately bound up in such systems. The fragmented human image created by
modernist science has long been resisted by some psychologists and there are indications
that cognitivism is approaching a time of fundamental change and re-assessment.
Over the last two decades there have been calls for psychological research to
be re-contextualised in a framework of human motives. For example, even though
most research on cognition and emotion is still heavily biased towards the primacy
of cognition, there are now moves towards treating cognition and emotion together.
While there are signs of change such as these, the position is still significantly
short of the Buddhist view of emotion and cognition as inextricably entwined at
the heart of the human psyche. It should be noted, however, that this view has
in fact been been a clear if minor thread in Western psychological thinking, with
roots stretching back through Spinoza and Vico.
There are also signs that Buddhism
is indirectly contributing to a shift in the balance between reduction and holism
within cognitivism itself. The search for formal laws of rational mental life
has lead to the decontextualisation of cognition. Recent critiques advocating
a more naturalistic, phenomenal approach are apt to cite Buddhist thinkers and
philosophers who were influenced by Buddhism.
In the postmodern era, psychology
is moving towards a holist, contextualised view of mental life. Experience and
its biophysical vehicle are seen as different aspects of one system with mutually
evolved parts. Such a view resembles the doctrine of dependent origination and
is in line with developments within Western science more generally.
Buddhism
advances a non-dual view of mind and brain and of the necessary integration of
cognition with the emotions and the will. As a consequence, it rarely treats cognition
in isolation since it does not operate in isolation. To do otherwise would perceive
boundaries where none exist. The doctrine of dependent origination holds that
the flow of experience is bound up with the activity of the body and the mind
in a dynamic cycle of interacting causes. The emergent and self-maintaining structures
produced by this cycle participate in what Whitehead has called the 'creative
advance of nature'. Since there is such an affinity between process metaphysics
and Buddhism, it is not surprising that Buddhist psychology emphasises that cognition,
emotion and the will participate together in this creative advance. The purpose
of this emphasis on the continuity and interdependence of psycho-physical causality
is to increase awareness of the cycles of causation, both mental and physical,
within which the mind arises and is sustained.
Critiques of modern psychology
and its reductionist assumptions often note the weakness of its account of psycho-physical
continuity and the negative image of the human condition it promotes. Postmodern
psychology will be postcognitive psychology; a pluralist discourse in which cognitivism
will participate with other traditions to create a more complete science of the
mind. It is in this spirit that it has been suggested here that Buddhism may interact
with cognitivism and thus play a role in the development of postmodern psychology.
The final section of this paper looks briefly at one issue that this role may
raise, which is the moral dimension of scientific psychology.
Consequences
of interaction.
The interactions discussed here suggest Buddhism may interact
with cognitivism as a kind of metatheory. However, given the diversity of Buddhism
on the one hand and the volatility of cognitivism on the other, it is unrealistic
to expect to reach any final state which resolves the incompatibilities and confirms
the similarities between them. Rather, continuing efforts can be made to seek
in Buddhism both an internal and external indicators for the development of postmodern
science of the mind.
The postmodern turn has seen a critical re-assessment
of science. Instead of the uniquely powerful investigation of nature, the idea
is now about that science is but one of many culturally supported knowledge systems.
Philosophers propose a range of views of science as an epistemological craft or
practice with its own culture and fashions. Science is no longer privileged, scientific
theories and the methods generated by them are not absolute and cummulative. They
are provisional and subject to radical revision; not just in the Popperian sense
of disproof, but in the deeper sense of being metaphors for a reality that cannot
be directly known.
Science has meaning within a particular condition of culture.
This hermeneutic stance is perhaps more true for psychological science, given
the essential subjectivity of its subject, than it is for the biological or physical
sciences. Even highly formalised cognitivist theories, such as those of Marr and
Nishihara on early visual processing, are probably beyond the reach of objective
disproof. They may, nevertheless, be productive when placed within a larger interpretive
framework.
Generally speaking, philosophers of cognitivism have dealt with
the plausibility of its findings and their implications for classic issues in
the philosophy of mind. They have been less concerned with the effects of its
efforts to adopt the methods and assumptions of positivist science. One of these
effects is a tendency to develop elaborate theories of isolated parts of the mind
while at the same time down-playing the nature of the whole. As one critical observer
has put it: "modern psychology ... remains a system of observations and hypotheses,
already compromised in advance by the fact that those who practice it are ignorant
of the profounder nature of the phenomena they set out to study".
Now
cognitivists might respond that rather than being ignorant of the mind's profounder
nature, they merely have realistic aims. Furthermore, reductive methodology can
be justified because of its success in other sciences. Accordingly, psychology
seeks to isolate and formalise a particular level of mental life rather than to
examine the mind in toto and at a more naturalistic grain.
But this is to import
into psychology what Whitehead called 'the fallacy of misplaced concreteness'
and to suppose that scientific explanation must necessarily be in terms of formal
descriptions of atomistic particulars set in a static framework. As Whitehead
put it, nature cannot be held still in order to be observed. Doing so obscures
aspects of nature carried by patterns of organic relations, and the mind is just
such an aspect. While reductionism is effective for disclosing the vehicle for
these patterns, it is of strictly limited use in understanding how they participate
in the activity of the whole. Such parts as reductionism discloses need to be
contextualised in an framework or image of how the whole system acts. Within such
a framework the physical, biological and psychological dynamics of the natural
order are understood as parts of a mutually evolved system of organic relations.
There is no need to search within this system for a particular level of organisation
with privileged causal status,. Cognitivism's computational theory or the fundamental
material grain of reality that was the grail of classical physics are chimerical
objectives for science, since they correspond to nothing in reality.
Postmodern
science is revising the place of the human phenomenon within the natural order.
The eclipse of modernist science has created a productive metaphysical vacuum.
Within it is growing the image of the mind as bound up with intrinsically self-organising
patterns of biological and physical order. The human phenomenon is increasingly
a focus in areas of science as diverse as cosmology and chemistry. Both Heidegger's
analysis of technology's impact on human experience of the environment and Bergson's
views on the experience of time are being re-examined, in respect of their implications
for epistemology and psychology. Most importantly, Whiteheadian process philosophy
is recognised as particularly appropriate for describing the mutually evolved
network of organic causation within which mental life arises and is sustained.
Appreciating this network more fully will provide a framework with in which the
restrictive dichotomy between monism and dualism can be replaced by a mutualist
view.
The mutualist view is that mind, brain and the patterns of activity which
link them are supported within a web of mutually evolved organic relations. Although
evolution is not an issue in many forms of Buddhism, this mutualist view has a
great deal in common with the process metaphysics that is compatible with all
forms. Accordingly, interaction with Buddhism could promote a broader organic
contextualisation of cognitivism. It is significant in this context to note that
recent critiques of cognitivism have objected to the neglect of the biological
context of cognition.
As well as any theoretical changes that interaction between
Buddhism and cognitivism would entail, it would also raise the issue of the moral
dimension of psychological science . As Bohm has put it: "A postmodern science
should not separate matter and consciousness and should not therefore, separate
facts, meaning and value."
Presently a common view is that science only
deals with epistemic values. If moral or ethical values do become attached to
science, they are side effects of its influence on human concerns. Ethical, utilitarian
and other non-epistemic values are secondary and contingently rather than necessarily
attached to science. It is the uses to which science and technology are put that
have moral consequences; thereby, and only thereby, does science enter the moral
arena. Cognitivism, inheriting this positivist model of science, thus implicitly
takes itself to be the rational and systematic acquisition of intrinsically value-free
knowledge.
This view has, however, recently come under critical scrutiny. Part
of the postmodern reappraisal of psychological science is the recognition that
science inherently participates in the wider realm of culturally defined value.
More deeply, the suggestion has been made that science taps a value system preceding
that of human culture and one that is necessarily related to ethical and moral
issues in ways that Buddhism has emphasised.
While the value dimension of cognitivism
is contingent rather than necessary, the value dimension of Buddhism is necessary
rather than contingent. Buddhism's concern with value arises from the doctrine
of dependent origination and the place it gives to human action within the natural
order. Human action is intrinsically value-laden by virtue of necessary cause
and effect relationships that impose no qualitative break between physical, psychological
and ethical matters. All action has a moral content over and above that stemming
from any human code. Putting it broadly, there is no right and wrong but rather
action and its consequences. Accordingly, Buddhist psychological insight is inherently
value laden. It is in this sense that interaction between cognitivism, supposedly
a value-free science, with Buddhism, an intrinsically value-laden practice, will
raise moral questions.
Buddhism does not distinguish ethical and physical domains
in the same way as Kant's distinction between physical laws and moral precepts.
It may be for this reason that Buddhism often features in current discussions
of environmental impact of technocractic culture. This impact has to do with running
counter to patterns patterns of organic causality that presently lie outside the
understanding of science and technology. These patterns include the causal links
of mind and body which Buddhism maintains that it is possible to understand more
fully by the training of awareness. This is one of the reasons why Buddhist psychology
does not exist as a separate discipline: "....the nature of psychological
phenomena cannot be completely separated from the underlying concept of reality
in Buddhism - questions about the structure of the universe and the nature of
man .....relate to physical and moral as well as psychological phenomena."
The doctrine of dependent origination gathers mind, action and material reality
within a single system. In this respect, Buddhist views will make a distinctive
contribution to the debate on the values implicit in cognitivism and in science
more generally.
Conclusions
This paper has emphasised how Buddhism may contribute
to the development of postmodern psychology. It is clear, however, that influences
will move in both directions, which may be to the advantage of Buddhism. Many
Buddhist traditions rely so heavily on exceptional individuals that they tend
to become arcane and authoritarian. This exerts an unhelpful selective influence
on those who would take an interest in Buddhism. It discourages those who value
the libertarian and humanitarian provenance of scientific culture and attracts
those who seek, often uncritically, an alternative to an uncongenial scientific
view. Informed interaction with cognitivism may serve to make Buddhism seem less
esoteric to those who would otherwise reject it.
There is also the possibility
that new and useful additions to Buddhist thought will occur. Cognitivism is,
for example, more informed about the biophysical nature of the brain and offers
a more innovative, open methodology for investigating the mind. Cognitivism, like
any science, is in a permanent state of change while Buddhism is stable by comparison.
While Cognitivism evolves rapidly through the conjectures and refutations of the
scientific method, Buddhist teachings and practices change slowly, grounded as
they are in a vastly more extended historical perspective. Buddhism, aiming to
promote more skilful living, is practised as well as studied. Cognitivism, a supposedly
value free inquiry into psychological reality, is studied rather than practised.
Buddhism has the purpose of helping those who practice it to lead a more satisfactory
life. Practitioners of cognitivism, by contrast, aim to add to knowledge of the
mind qua object and do not expect to change much in the process. For cognitivism
the theory changes while the cognitivist remains the same; for Buddhism, the reverse
is the case.
In the postmodern condition, even such major differences are no
barrier to exploring the many points of similarity which, apart from being productive,
may also be desirable. Science has replaced religion as the modernist world view.
In the process it has impoverished the image of the human condition within in
the natural order. The Enlightenment may have removed a morass of repressive dogma,
but a lot of security and comprehensibility of the world went with it. Instead
of being special and valuable, the human condition is now merely an accidental
and possible perverse complication in a universe which in reality merely comprises
what Whitehead called the "meaningless hurrying of indifferent matter".
Such a change cannot occur without psychological consequences. Enlightenment in
the Buddhist sense is rather different. Bringing these two senses of enlightenment
together in a postmodern science of the mind will help to replace human consciousness
within the natural order.