Toward a Buddhist Philosophy of Science
Science is the
cornerstone of the European-American culture that has transformed the entire globe
over the last few centuries. Buddhism is a deeply rooted religious tradition of
Asia, now emerging as a powerful global voice. Science and Buddhism both address
the nature of human experience, but in quite different ways. Science elaborates
and refines a collection of interconnected theories, facts, procedures, and equipment,
constituting an ever more powerful tool for working with and in the world. Buddhism
focusses more on the mind and how our way of thinking affects our experience.
Both science and Buddhism show how everyday appearances arise from underlying
structures. By understanding these structures one gains new freedom, to choose
among alternatives by working effectively with the cause and effect relations.
Science has given us great power to understand and change the world. But this
power has also let us create new and bigger problems for ourselves. Without examining
how the dynamics of mind underlies our experience, it might seem that the evolutionary
path of science and technology is a matter beyond our choice or responsibility.
But the profound insights of Buddhism reveal that our perceptions and actions
arise in habitual self-reinforcing cycles, and the methods taught in the Buddhist
tradition enable us to intervene in these cycles.
Science and technology in
some form or other, which is to say some way of thinking about and working with
the world, are a fundamental dimension of human existence. Modern science has
blossomed by driving the refinement of ideas through public debate grounded in
clear evidence. Buddhism shows the dynamics underlying any such evolving pattern
of experience, and provides tools to open these patterns to boundless freedom
and joy.
Here I explore some dimensions of science where Buddhism might be
able to open new possibilities:
This essay is being written by Jim Kukula.
Introductory Sketch of Buddhism
Buddhism
got started around 500 BC when Siddhartha Gautama, the sage of the Sakya clan,
got disgusted by his life and circumstances and left home to devote himself to
meditation. Some years later he experienced profound realization and began teaching,
eventually accumulating a substantial following around the Ganges valley in India.
The path he taught consisted of a code of conduct, a variety of meditation techniques,
and doctrines about the nature of the world and humanity.
This school plugged
along in a small way for a couple hundred years. Then Emperor Ashoka around 300
BC converted to Buddhism. He worked to promote Buddhism across his empire, which
extended through most of modern day India and beyond into Pakistan etc. He also
sent Buddhist missionaries to distant places such as Greece. Buddhism continued
to grow in India, with ups and downs, over the next centuries. By 700 AD there
were several great Buddhist universities in India with over 10,000 students each.
Buddhism spread to Sri Lanka, Burma, Cambodia, and Indonesia. Buddhism also spread
to the northwest, into Afghanistan and up into Turkestan, and from there along
the silk route into China. Buddhism reached China perhaps in 200AD. Buddhism got
to Japan around 700AD, and Tibet about the same time.
Buddhism coexisted with
other local religions in most places, e.g. Vedic religion in India, and Taoism
and Confucianism in China. There tended to be a lot of borrowing back and forth
across religions over the centuries. Buddhism even picked up elements of Greek
culture from the remains of the Alexandrian empire around Afghanistan. For example,
the typical statues of Buddhas are based on Greek sculptures of Apollo.
Eventually
the spread of Islam from the West in the period 700-1300 AD wiped out Buddhism
in India and the Northwest, but Buddhism continued to thrive in Ceylon, Burma,
Cambodia, China, Japan, Tibet, and Mongolia. With this temporal and geographic
scope, Buddhism is clearly one of the great world religions. As one might expect,
Buddhism has accumulated a very wide spectrum of philosophical schools. I hope
my quick sketch here will not be too far out on the fringe.
The core of the
Buddha's teaching is that suffering arises from confusion, from the emotional
turmoil caused by this confusion, and from the unskillful actions driven by that
mix. The path taught by the Buddha attempts to liberate beings from suffering,
addressing unskillful action with a code of conduct, emotional turmoil with meditation,
and confusion with doctrine about the nature of things.
The doctrines about
the nature of things are perhaps most relevant to the discussions here. Our general
widespread confusion is one that takes objects to behave and exist in ways that
they actually don't. We tend to perceive and conceptualize things as if they existed
as stable, enduring, isolated, and well-defined. But in fact things are constantly
changing and only exist as a parts of patterns, interrelated with other things.
The Buddha's teachings on the nature of things were memorized and interpreted
and eventually written down in various ways, forming classically 18 different
schools. Typically these analyse the objects of everyday life by reducing them
to composite structures built up from elements, variously categorized by the different
schools. Generally the categories fall coarsely into the five heaps of form, feeling,
perception, conception, and consciousness. The elements in these categories are
generally held to exist only momentarily, continuous existence being an illusion
based on the successive momentary appearance of similar elementary components.
By 100 AD or so the Madhyamika school had emerged, championed by Nagarjuna.
Nagarjuna argued that even these various elementary components do not exist as
distinct isolated well-defined entities, but only exist by virtue of participating
in a pattern of interrelationship.
I hope this very short explanation serves
to reduce confusion and does not create confusion or emotional turmoil or lead
to unskillful action!!!
Philosophy
of Science
Science and Society
Science and its metaphysical foundations
are of crucial importance today. The technological transformation of the world,
guided by scientific principles, is an ongoing process of staggering impact. These
principles are applied not only to blatantly mechanical systems such as automobiles,
but also guide our thinking and acting in social situations. A clearer understanding
of the nature of science can help us with many key contemporary issues.
"
Our actions today are creating problems of ever greater magnitude for which we
do not have clear solutions. Examples include the accumulation of nuclear wastes,
changes in the atmospheric composition due to industrial by-products, depletion
of non-renewable resources such as petroleum, depeletion of potentially renewable
resources such as fresh water, and extinction of biological species. Our actions
that create these problems are so tightly interwoven with our way of life that
to avoid these actions would require major changes in that way of life. Thus we
are faced with a very high stakes decision. A key factor in that decision is an
estimate of future growth in human knowledge and capability. Is it wise to choose
a course of action that relies on substantial future scientific and technology
progress to avoid catastrophic consequences? Can we rely on science to come to
the rescue?
" Sometimes scientific evidence appears that points out the
need to take unpleasant action in order to avoid some potentially severe negative
result. For example, there is evidence that global carbon dioxide emissions must
be reduced dramatically if negative climatic changes are to be avoided. How strong
must scientific evidence and consensus be in order to make such difficult choices?
Does science ever reach absolute certainty about cause-effect relationships in
the world? Does the need for further research ever stop? If the scientific debates
continue endlessly, how can science be used to inform decision making?
"
Science generates knowledge which enables action through development of technology.
New knowledge can give us new capabilities to perform destructive actions, or
actions with very uncertain consequences. For example, advances in biotechnology
such as genetic engineering give us the power to introduce new species. We may
also be able to genetically engineer human beings. If we decide we do not want
to perform certain classes of actions, should we avoid generating scientific knowledge
that could enable those actions?
" Once technology has been developed
with great destructive potential, such as nuclear weaponry, is it wise or practical
to attempt to restrict the dissemination of the scientific knowledge that provides
the basis for that technology? Won't independent scientific progress just regenerate
that knowledge? On the other hand, technology can be developed with great positive
potential, such as a new medicine. Is it necessarily unethical to restrict the
use of that technology or to restrict the flow of its underlying knowledge, e.g.
to protect the profits returned to the investors who funded the development of
that technology? Can it ever be good or right to block the spread of truth?
"
The generation of scientific knowledge itself involves performing a variety of
actions. These actions may be expensive or ethically negative. For example, many
scientific experiments involve pain, sickness, or untimely death for human or
animal subjects. Projects such as interplanetary expeditions involve huge government
expenditure. What is a wise, appropriate price to pay for scientific knowledge?
" Institutional decision making is informed by a variety of expert opinions.
The authority given to these experts is often derived from their credentials acquired
in the scientific community. For example, scientists give expert testimony in
judicial proceedings. How should the authority of scientific expertise be weighed
against other sources of expertise? How much danger is there of such power corrupting
the validity of scientific credentials? How can we protect ourselves against this
danger?
" Not all knowledge is scientific. Other institutions cultivate
and transmit knowledge, most notably religious institutions. These different bodies
of knowledge are generally not mutually consistent. Scientific and religious institutions
often view each other's knowledge as being invalid. Can a healthy society support
multiple inconsistent bodies of knowledge, or must such conflicts be resolved
in favor of some single self-consistent body of knowledge? Should invalid knowledge
be tolerated? Should non-scientific knowledge be tolerated?
" Not all
institutions that claim to be scientific are in fact scientific. Indeed, scientific
institutions somtimes suffer lapses such as fraud. How can valid scientific knowledge
be distinguished from fraudulent or false science?
What is Science?
Science
is a complex human enterprise, involving many activities such as:
" a
laboratory technician figuring out what's wrong with a piece of equipment and
how to fix it
" a scientist deciding which data to include in a research
paper and how to interpret it
" a scientific journal editor consulting
with referees on whether or not a submitted paper merits publication
"
a faculty committee planning the undergraduate curriculum, which topics need to
be covered and what order will work best.
" corporate managers weighing
potential return on investment from various possible research and development
efforts
These activities leave their marks on the world, from the scientist's
immediate surroundings with journals lining library shelves and laboratories filled
with equipment and materials, to industry with equipment and materials on a much
larger scale, to the world at large with the pervasive presence of technology
and its byproducts. The effects of science are not merely material - science transforms
human experience. Our outlook is not only changed by the broader range of experience
enabled by transportation and communication technology. We live surrounded by
ever more sophisticated machinery whose behavior constantly trains our perceptions
and expectations. The ideas about the world developed by scientists are widely
taught in schools and popular literature and have become an integral part of human
culture around the world.
Science and technology have made spectacular progress
since the scientific revolution 300 years ago. Physics outines the detailed structures
of atoms and stars. Biochemistry traces the contruction of proteins from their
DNA blueprint. Technology based on science puts men on the moon and ten million
transistors on a chip. Given this solid track record, what room is there for questions
about the nature of science?
To be able to do a thing successfully does not
imply a thorough understanding of the processes that participate in that doing.
The best scientists in the world don't understand the complex physiology engaged
in a basketball shot, but that doesn't get in Michael Jordan's way! A key tactic
in science is specialization. A scientist studying the structure of bat's wings
is not liable to be very knowledgeable about stellar evolution. Disciplines such
as psychology and anthropology study human behavior and social institutions, but
have not achieved the level of reliability and predictability achieved in the
physical science, due in part no doubt to the complexity of the object of study.
Science however is a manifestation of human behavior and social institutions.
A thorough scientific understanding of science is a very tall project! The best
psychologists and anthropologists might have some small inkling of what is going
on with science. Just like Michael Jordan probably knows very little about the
anatomy of the optic nerve despite being a skilled user of that apparatus, it
is unreasonable to expect an expert in aerodynamics to have a particularly enlightened
understanding of how science works. Our great accomplishments in science do not
imply any similar depth of understanding of the nature of science.
Metaphysical
Foundations
My main focus here will be on relationship between the scientific
description of the world and the world itself. The scientific description includes
raw records of experimental data, theoretical formulations of the general structure
of phenomena, and everything in between. It is embodied in scientific journals,
operating manuals for laboratory equipment, notebooks, chalkboards, videotapes,
and the evanescent vocal performances of scientists in lecture and dialog. This
description is constantly evolving as scientific activity proceeds. One simple
and common notion of science is that this evolution is progressing or could progress
toward some ultimately ideal description, a description that would be perfectly
satisfactory. Much scientific activity is focussed on finding and fixing errors
in the current scientific description. The ultimate description would have no
errors, so no more fixes would be needed. Is a perfectly error-free description
of the world possible? If not, can a description be created all of whose errors
can be safely and comfortably neglected? If all descriptions are alike in being
erroneous, is there any valid criterion for selecting a description to guide action
in the world?
The discipline of philosophy of science has developed around
various ways to address these questions. This being a specialized discipline,
most people, even most scientists, are unaware of the variety of positions taken
by the various schools. Occasionally results or controversies will spill out into
the public eye, as with the current "Science War" debates, triggered
by books such as Gross and Levitt's Higher Superstition. Ultimately a Buddhist
philosophy of science could add a new and valuable voice to this conversation.
This will require responses to each of the principal positions held by the various
philosophies of science. What I hope to do in this essay is merely outline some
of the basic difficulties that any philosophy of science must address, and to
indicate how a Buddhist perspective can contribute positively.
The Relevance
of Buddhism
The Buddhist tradition is over 2500 years old. Certainly when Shakyamuni
Buddha taught, he did not discuss differential equations, quantum fields, quarks,
etc. Nor did he discuss the scientific method, laboratory procedures, peer review,
etc. So it might seem that Buddhism wouldn't have anything substantial to say
about science. But both Buddhism and science grow out of questioning and examining
the nature of the world and our existence. Buddhist philosophers starting with
Shakyamuni Buddha have closely examined the role our ideas about the world play
in the ongoing evolution of our experence in the world.
The
world tends to be full of uncomfortable surprises. We humans apply a lot of effort,
trying to protect ourselves from these surprises. Much of this effort involves
rearranging the world, such as growing food, building houses, etc. We also build
up ideas about the world, classifying and naming objects, and noting the regularities
in their behavior. Once we know how to predict eclipses they are not so surprising
or frightening. While these efforts are successful to a large degree, still rude
surprises continue to intervene. On such occasions we might decide to investigate
things a bit more deeply, to find the hole to be able to patch it. The world turns
out not to be exactly the arrangement of objects that we thought it was. How is
it then? Our investigation might proceed in a variety of directions.
Impermanence
We
work hard to arrange things in some satisfactory way. At some point we might actually
succeed. But the next day, things have changed. The paint peels, the fruit rots,
the cloth frays. Youth ages, health turns to sickness, then death. What is the
nature of change? How can it be, that what is a fact on one day is not a fact
the next day?
The Paradox
Thinking about the nature of change has a very
deep history both in the scientific tradition going back to Zeno's paradoxes and
in the Buddhist tradition. It is worthwhile to study this matter closely. At one
point in time we can truly say, "X is true", and then some time later
we can truly say, "X is false". This mystery is traditionally illustrated
by a variety of ways to fill in the blank X. Zeno tells the story of Achilles,
the fastest human, chasing a tortoise, a much slower animal. When Achilles sets
off, the tortoise is on the other side of the field, some 100 yards distant. At
that time we would truly say, "Achilles has not caught the tortoise."
Some time later we would expect to be able to say, "Achilles has caught the
tortoise." In Indian philosophy a classical way to fill in for X is to consider
the growth of a seed into a sprout. At first we can say, "The seed has not
sprouted," then later we say, "The seed has sprouted."
I would
like to continue the discussion in the abstract form of "X" and "not
X". This is a common scientific move from concrete to abstract and mathematical.
Rather than examing science from a Buddhist perspective, do I not by such a move
instead introduce a scientific approach into Buddhism? But such a move is native
to Buddhism. The Buddha was asked whether his teaching wouldn't be distorted and
falsified if translated into other languages. The Buddha replied, "No,"
that his teaching, the holy Dharma, should be translated to be made more easily
understood by whatever audience was at hand. Buddhism for a scientific audience
needs to be translated into a scientific language. Furthermore the great Buddhist
philosopher Nagarjuna acknowledges the validity of using concepts for discursive
purposes without those concepts themselves being granted any more that provisional
validity. So, on with X...
I want to look more closely at how it could be
that at one time X is true and then at some later time X is false. There must
be some last time when X is true - let's call that A. Similarly there must be
some earliest time when X is false, which we can call B. Now, what is the temporal
relation between A and B? Is A before B? Is A after B? Are A and B actually the
same time? But none of these possibilities makes sense. If A and B are the same
time, or if A is after B, then X is both true and false for at least an instant
of time, which can't happen. But if A is before B, then there is a time right
between these when X is neither true nor false, which can't happen either!
One
classical resolution of this paradox is to claim that change cannot actually happen.
If X is true at one time, then X is always true. If it looks like X becomes false,
then this appearance of becoming is illusory. What really exists, exists permanently,
changelessly. The rude surprises of life are in fact illusory. The cure is to
free oneself of this illusion, to train oneself and transform oneself so one's
experience is only that of the eternal realm of unchanging truth.
Mathematical
Physics
At the heart of physics, at the heart of science, lies the differential
calculus of Newton and Leibniz. Since its origin some 300 years ago this calculus
has been elaborated and refined. Careful methods of reasoning now permit more
sophisticated resolutions of the paradox of change.
From a mathematical physics
perspective, the paradox arises from a flaw in reasoning. It is not valid to claim
that, "There must be some last time A when X is true." Physics models
time as real numbers. Real numbers are built up starting with integers like 1,
2, 3, then adding rationals like 1/2 and 2/3, and finally filling in the infinitesimal
spaces between neighboring rationals with irrationals like pi and the square root
of 2. Not every bounded set of real numbers has a maximal element. For example,
consider the set of all real numbers greater than 0 and less than 2. Pick any
number N in the set. N must be less than 2, because it is in the set. Pick another
number M halfway between N and 2. M is still less than 2, so it is also in our
set. M is greater than N, so N could not have be the maximal element of our set.
Whatever N we might propose to be a maximal element, we can always construct M
in this way so that M is bigger than N yet still in the set, still less than 2.
So this is an example of a bounded set of real numbers with no maximal element.
Sets of times, just like sets of numbers, need not have maximal or minimal
elements, even when bounded. Since the paradox of change depended on the existence
of such maximal elements, their nonexistence resolves the paradox.
Metastability
Real
numbers turn out upon further study to be quite strange objects. As mathematics
continues to develop, families of alternative systems with subtly different properties
have been explored. For example, model theory opens the door to nonstandard analysis
which introduces infinitesimal quantities. Which number system provides the correct
treatment for time?
A pragmatic approach to this question is to look at the
nature of measurement. To understand better how it is possible for X to be true
at one time and then to be false at some later time, let us consider the construction
of a measurement device that can tell us at what times X is true and at what times
is it false. Whether we are to deal with runners and reptiles or with seeds and
sprouts, the modern way to build a measurement device is to translate phenomena
into voltages. So let us suppose that we can arrange suitable electrodes and amplifiers
so we have a signal on a wire with positive voltage when X is true, otherwise
X is false. We want to measure the time when X changes from true to false.
The
fundamental problem here is one of converting a continuous quantity to a digital
one. A measurement is recorded as a number, for example "1.95". After
many measurements and an analysis of experimental procedures, an estimate of experimental
error will be added to this measurement when it is reported, for example "+/-
0.01". But it will be enough if our measurement process can somehow generate
the simple result "1.95". One approach would be to let some clock run
as long as X is true, and turn it off when X becomes false. So the time when X
became false can be reported by simply reading the clock after it stops. If the
clock uses an analog display, then the experimenter must examine the clock hand
position relative to the dial and decide which mark the hand lies closest to.
It is somewhat awkward to have a human decision intervene right at the crucial
point where our time measurement is to be performed. This obscures things right
where we are trying to make them clear; it seems to resolve the paradox with a
mystery. To avoid this obscurity, let us use a digital clock instead. We can just
record the digital clock reading directly onto a computer disk to be incorporated
into the experimental report without any mysterious human decisions involved.
Curiously, it turns out to be impossible to build any such device with complete
reliability. Just as a human experimenter might have trouble deciding how to record
the time when it falls right between two marks, any physical device will have
a sticking point, where things will jam up if X happens to switch from true to
false just as the digital clock is flipping digits. This is a classic problem,
called "metastability", in the design of digital circuits. Actually
the problem is far more widespread than just digital circuit design. Anytime a
continuous set of possibilities has to be cut into discrete parts, there is always
some bit of trouble.
Consider negotiating an intersection controlled by a
traffic light. Most of the time things go smoothly. But every once in a while,
the light turns yellow when one is at an awkward spot, not obviously so far along
as to easily clear the intersection before the red, but not so distant either
to allow for a gentle stop. Indecision arises, to go or to stop? For different
folks this point of indecision will arise at different distances from the intersection.
But between the go zone and the stop zone there is always difficult boundary.
Similarly, when people pass each other moving in opposite directions, there is
always the choice of passing on the right or the left. Or which person should
pass through the door first?
It may seem peculiar to be using a facet of digital
systems design as a means to illuminate the nature of change. But in fact digital
systems such as computers were actually first envisioned as purely conceptual
devices, to clarify issues in mathematics such as the nature of numbers and methods
of reasoning. The engineering of computer systems provides a mirror for the general
human effort to build a stable, reliable, predictable world. Often this mirror
can show more explicitly and clearly the problems and paradoxes that arise but
obscurely and mysteriously in the general effort.
Metastability is the pragmatic
manifestation of the paradox of change. It is not possible to build a device that
can with perfect reliability report the time at which some feature of the world
changes. Rude and awkward suprises seem to be unavoidable!
Causation
The
sort of description science strives for is not just a catalog of events but an
explanation of those events. We want to understand why things happen the way they
do. To achieve this understanding we start by observing regular patterns of appearance.
For example, every year as the days get longer in the spring season, the temperatures
rise and trees grow leaves. Noticing this regularity does not yet by itself yield
an understanding of the causative relationship between these events. If we observe
that event C always happens soon after event B, we cannot validly infer that event
B causes event C. There may be some prior event A that causes both B and C, with
no causal relation between B and C.
How can we investigate to determine what
causal relations lie behind the patterns of correlated events we observe? Scientific
experiments are a powerful procedure for investigating causal relations. To experimentally
determine if event B causes event C, the key requirement is that we be able to
freely generate event B. If event C occurs each time we generate B, but does not
occur when we don't generate B, we can be confident that B indeed causes C. If
instead we observe occurrences of C only after spontaneous occurrences of B but
never after the occurrences of B that we freely generate, then we can be confident
that C is not caused by B, but instead caused by some prior A that also causes
B in a parallel chain.
Note the complementary relation between free will and
causation revealed by examining the experimental method. Often free will and causation
are held to be in conflict: if events arise due to causation from prior events,
then how can human actors freely perform actions? But now we see that in fact
causation is meaningless without free will; without free will, causation cannot
be distinguished from correlation. And conversely, without causation free will
would also be meaningless; without causation, free will could not engage the world,
the chain of events trigger by free action would be abruptly terminated and action
would be utterly ineffective.
Curiously the scientific description of the
world does not include the free will of the scientific experimenter, even though
that free will is an essential requirement for the generation of that description.
It's a bit like the blind spot in the visual field caused by the connection of
the optic nerve to the retina. The optic nerve is an essential requirement for
the effective functioning of the retina, yet the retina is blind just at that
point.
Experimental procedures can attempt to avoid relying on free will.
There is indeed a danger that the occurrence or non-occurrence of some event A
will influence the decision of the experimenter to generate event B or not. If
A also in parallel causes C, then the experimenter will observe that C occurs
just when B is generated and so conclude that B causes C. But this conclusion
is fallacious, because the generation of B was not in fact free, but caused by
A through a causal chain of events that include the experimenter's decision to
generate B.
In order to avoid such errors, experimenters often rely on some
sort of mechanical randomized process to govern the decision of whether to generate
B or not in any particular repetition of the experiment. For example, a coin toss
might determine when a particular patient is given a new test drug or a placebo.
In order to prevent the experimenter's observations from being distorted by expectations
driven by the outcome of this decision process, the experimenter can be kept ignorant
of the outcome. This is the widely used "double blind" procedure.
While
double blind procedures are doubtless effective at reducing the distortion of
experimental results due to biases of the experimenters, the procedure still relies
on an essential element of free will. The experimental procedure requires that
a link be established between some random process such as a coin toss, and the
generation or non-generation of some event in the experiment. One could interpret
"heads" to mean "give the placebo", or alternative one could
interpret "heads" to mean "give the test drug". For the experimental
results to validly indicate whether casual relations exist or not, the choice
between these interpretations must be freely made.
Thus we see that free will
is an essential requirement for discovering the causal relations in the world.
But the descriptions that are constructed as a result of these discoveries do
not include free will. Free will is an inevitable blind spot in any scientific
explanation of how the world works.
Compositionality
The
everyday objects around us are assembled out of various other objects. For example
an automobile is built out of a chassis, an engine, a body, etc. If we think carefully
about this situation, we will run into a variety of puzzles and paradoxes. What
is the value of reflecting on such difficulties?
Our habitual way of thinking
about the world is to conceive of it as a collection of various objects, which
relate to each other and to ourselves. We try to arrange the situation with ourselves
relating in some stable way among the various objects. Somehow though problems
are constantly arising, and when we are not somewhat desparately trying to patch
things up to return to some manageable level of stability, we are worrying about
where and when the next outbreak of unwelcome surprises will come and how can
we be prepared to respond.
So it really does seem counterproductive to go
looking for trouble. Life is difficult enough already without anyone trying to
topple over nice cozy arrangements such as automobiles whose engines are so neatly
bolted to their chassis. Is the object of such an exercise to prod us into yet
another weekend repair chore, hunting down the aisles of hardware stores looking
for yet stronger glue to secure our lives from these latest assaults? Let's just
lay back and drink lemonade instead and forget the whole exercise.
The goals
of Buddhist practise and of ordinary behavior are not different. Beings just want
to be happy, and perform what seems to them the most effective actions to become
and stay happy. Despite such universal intentions, the world seems quite filled
with suffering. Despite everone's cultivation of happiness, unhappiness prevails.
The Buddhist diagnosis of this situation is quite simple: the vast majority of
beings are confused about what sorts of actions have what sorts of effects. The
actions they perform, in order to secure happiness, actually generate unhappiness.
The Buddhist path is a training in methods that truly produce happy results.
Part of this training is to cultivate an understanding of the ways that common
confused approaches lead instead to suffering. One needs to understand what is
confused about confusion. A classic instance of confused action is rigidly clinging
to a conceptualization of the world as some particular arrangement of objects
with various relationships to each other and oneself. If one can see that any
such conceptualization is of only limited validity, that the more rigidly one
clings to such fixed ideas the more pain results from the inevitable mismatches,
then one may become more able to catch oneself as one's habits again drive one
into such conceptual clinging, and gradually train oneself to develop a mental
pliability that can freely take up and let go of conceptualizations, with the
openness to allow the value and use of each to display themselves.
The paradoxes
considered here are not new. Various versions appear in the classical philosophical
traditions around the world. Any way of thinking has somehow to make peace with
these paradoxes. Whatever solution is settled upon is inevitably unstable, but
various defense mechanisms can be cultivated to prevent the logical problems from
destabilizing the patterns of thinking that form one of the fundamental subsystems
of any culture. Modern scientific culture has its instabilities and defense mechanisms
like any other. By bringing these to light and recognizing them we may become
more able to weigh their costs and benefits and choose among alternatives more
wisely and compassionately.
So let's look at some object like an automobile.
Perhaps this automobile is connected to a trailer. Does this combination of automobile
and trailer form some new object, an automobile-plus-trailer? Of course this is
just a game of semantics, of words and their meanings. But if it is just a game
of semantics to ask, "Is that an automobile-plus-trailer," isn't is
just as much a game to ask, "Is that an automobile?" Just like "automobile-plus-trailer"
is just a made-up word one can use to refer to an arrangement of an automobile
connected to a trailer, isn't "automobile" just a made-up word one can
use to refer to an arrangment of a body mounted on a chassis with an engine bolted
in and hooked to the wheels? Suppose you put an automobile in your garage, and
then pull the engine out and set it alongside. Is there still an automobile in
the garage? Is the engine still part of the automobile or are the automobile and
the engine now separate objects? Suppose you mount the engine in some other chassis-plus-body
and drive that new combination away. Is the chassis-plus-body still in the garage
an automobile? Does is still include the engine that was driven away? Suppose
we mount a new replacement engine in the chassis-plus-body in the garage. Is there
now an automobile in the garage, and is this new engine a part of it? Is this
automobile the same automobile that we started with in the garage?
In case
this all seems totally absurd, you might consider the problems that arise with
car theives, chop shops, and serial numbers. The black market thrives on ambiguity
and instability!
Here is another puzzle. Suppose we define a place-setting
to be a knife, a fork, and a spoon. Suppose we have a drawer containing four knives,
four forks, and four spoons. How many place-settings are in the drawer? The easy
answer is four, but wouldn't it be truer to say 64? Label the knives K1, K2, K3,
and K4, the forks F1, F2, etc. Wouldn't it be accurate to say that place-setting
K1+F1+S1 is a different place-setting than K1+F1+S2?
Reductionism
The more
one considers how it happens that some arrangements of smaller objects somehow
form a larger composite object whereas different arrangements form different larger
objects or no larger objects at all, the more one tries to understand just how
those larger objects come into existence or pass out of existence, the more one
is driven to the conclusion that these larger composite objects are not really
existing things that suddenly spring into being or vanish as the smaller objects
are rearranged. Instead it starts to get clearer that we think about and talk
about these larger objects as a sort of shorthand summary of lots of details concerning
the smaller objects and their arrangement, details that don't matter much anyway.
So if someone asks, "Is there an automobile in your garage?" the most
accurate reply might be something like, "There is an arrangement of pistons
and shock absorbers and metal panels and lots of other things, arranged in such
a way that you can climb in and drive it around, and it strongly resembles in
shape and substance other arrangements which people generally call 'automobile',
so using that commonplace shorthand way of speaking, yes, there is an automobile
in my garage." Of course such accuracy is mostly a waste of time.
But
such accuracy is not entirely a waste of time. If everyone understands what is
behind a statement like, "Yes, there is an automobile in my garage,"
then perhaps no one will be upset when the situation is actually a little bit
over into the grey area, so perhaps the automobile is not is the best repair,
perhaps some not quite essential component is missing, so when one person's expectations
are disappointed there is mutual understanding that words can never capture reality
so such disappointment is not entirely avoidable and need not be blamed on anyone,
so anger and a cycle of retribution need not be triggered.
If large composite
objects like automobiles "exist" merely as a conventional shorthand
way to summarize in a rough way some arrangement of smaller objects, what about
those smaller objects? Do they also exist in such a merely conventional fashion?
When your sunglasses fall out of your pocket as you cross the street and somebody's
Ford Expedition smashes them into pieces, maybe that's just a shorthand way of
saying 6000 pounds of steel, but such a real effect surely has some similarly
real cause!
The modern scientific answer to this puzzle is reductionism: while
automobiles and engines and pistons are just conventional names to summarize arrangments
of smaller objects, at some point there is an end to this process of examining
objects to discover how they are composed of smaller objects. A piston is composed
of a huge number of atoms, and the atoms themelves can be broken down further
into elementary particles such as electrons. An electron is not composed of smaller
particles, it just exists all by itself as just what it is, an electron. The real
true description of the world is that it is some evolving arrangement of elementary
particles. Of course this arrangement involves a mind-boggling mass of details,
so inevitably we have to talk about it with conventional shorthand terms, but
those terms don't refer to actually existing objects, merely to loosely defined
arrangements of elementary particles. This is the reductionist view of modern
science.
This reductionist view actually started to fall apart just as it
appear to finally have matured. Of Albert Einstein's famous three papers of 1905,
the paper on Brownian motion established the actual existence of atoms, while
the paper on the photoelectric effect gave a powerful boost to the nascent quantum
mechanics that undermined the foundations of that existence. But the reductionist
view runs into problems even before we run into quantum mechanics.
Suppose
the classical mechanical reductionist view were somehow correct. Suppose we somehow
managed to construct a perfect description of the world. This description, according
to the classical reductionist view, would consist of a list of particles and their
coordinates. Perhaps the description would even have the complete history of each
particle, the sequence of values of the coordinates as they evolved and will evolve
over time. This description being quite vast, we store it in a sophisticated high-powered
computer database. But there are some tough design problems in the way of constructing
this database. The database will just contain a set of records, something like
particle identification number
time x location y location z location
151900166
874999.30567 2803486.55483 -73384.59446 1036438658.22953
151900167 874999.30567
-1304857504.583299 205333.6895 142726658304.789433
The immediate problem is:
what measurement units and frame of reference should be used in the perfect description?
If I wanted to see where that Ford Expedition drove off to, I could just find
the coordinate for where your sunglasses where when they got smashed, find what
particle was just above that point a few inches, then jump ahead a couple of hours
and look up where that particle is now. But how can I find the coordinate where
your sunglasses got smashed? If I knew the label for one of the particles of your
sunglasses, maybe I could look up its location when they got smashed. Of course,
that particle has a very long history, perhaps billions of years, so there is
still the problem of knowing what time they got smashed.
So there is the first
problem with the reductionist view of the world. A description that consisted
merely of particles and coordinates would be quite useless. The only reality we
know is the conventional reality, including especially our own self. If one searched
our perfect reductionist database for any configuration of particles fitting the
description of "Ford Expedition smashing sunglasses", there might be
hundreds of matches. Some of these matches might even be on different planets,
on different galaxies, millions of years in the future. I want to know about the
events that are related to me, not to some similar arrangement of particles very
distant. To be useful, the database will have to somehow include the relationship
of the particles or coordinates to the user's experience in conventional terms.
Thus a perfect description must include conventional terms. These conventional
terms are essential to the description. The reductionist view of the world is
incomplete in an essential way.
The reductionist view proposes the ultimate
absolute existence of elementary particles and the nonexistence of composite objects.
We have seen that composite objects are essentially required in any adequate description
of the world, so one plank in the reductionist platform is flawed. The classical
Mahayana Buddhist philosopher Nagarjuna had already pointed out the flaw in the
other plank, the existence of elementary particles. The flowering of quantum mechanics
in this century has revealed much more complex phenomena underlying the appearance
of elementary particles. Nagarjuna simply pointed out that if such particles existed
they would have to have occupy some non-zero extent of space if things weren't
to just collapse in on itself, and any such non-zero extent is necessarily composite,
being divisible into smaller non-zero extents. With quantum mechanics, things
not collapsing on themselves is explained by Fermi-Dirac particle interchange
anti-symmetry. But such anti-symmetry undermines the existence of elementary particles
every bit as much as a non-zero extent would have. What really exists from a quantum
theory perspective is something like a collection of elementary particle fields.
The fields are what exist, the particles are just the appearance of the field.
But actually things are quite a bit thicker that this. The various particle
fields are interacting. The particles we observe are actually bundles of interacting
particles. If we try to peel apart these bundles, we find that the peeling apart
process never ends. This rude discovery was called the ultraviolet catastrophe.
Renormalization group theory was invented by Feynman, Schwinger, and Tomonaga
to compute appearances despite the nonexistence of the bare particles.
So
quantum mechanics has really given up on the existence of elementary particles.
The particles we observe can be analysed as excitations of coupled fields, but
those fields only exist as those appearances. The various modes of excitations
of these fields change depending on the situation. The elementary particles that
exist inside crystals are quite different from those that exist in a vaccuum.
For example, sound waves do not exist in a vaccuum, but do exist in crystals.
Sound waves are excitations of the crystals, and these excitations are quantized,
which is to say appear as collections of elementary particles, known as phonons.
Solid state physicists measure properties of phonons and use them to predict the
behavior of crystals. Thus these particles are quite real in the sense of having
clearly observable impact on human experience. Yet they exist only in the context
of a cystal, not in a vaccuum.
Even more curiously, phonons and electrons
interact. Thus, in a crystal, any excitation is really a combination of phonon
field and electron field in coupled oscillation. Generally the phonon or the electron
aspect dominates, so the excitation can be labelled "phonon" or "electron".
But at some frequencies there is a sort of mutual resonance, where the phonon
and electron field are working tightly together. In this case the excitation is
called an "exciton". As the frequency shifts, the modes of excitation
of the fields that compose the crystal shift smoothly from being phonon dominated
to a balance and then to electron dominated. The particles that appear vary smoothly
from phonons through excitons to electrons.
I certainly don't mean to hold
up any particular physics theory as being correct or incorrect. I bring up the
complexities of quantum mechanics merely to point out that, just as the reductionist
view understates the existence of composite objects, it also overstates the existence
of elementary particles. The conventional view, that objects like automobiles
just simply exist as they appear, very quickly runs into trouble as their behavior
reveals their composite nature. But as we try to pin down just what objects really
do exist, we find the project to be quite difficult. The closer we look, the more
complex the underlying phenomena appear.
Varieties
of Experience
There is a sense in which ordinary everyday reality is like a
dream or an illusion. The world discovered by science is also like a dream or
an illusion. At first glance these statements seem absurd. There is a world of
difference between dreaming that one falls off a tall building and actually falling
off a tall building! But the claim is that ordinary experience is like a dream,
not that it actually is a dream.
Our various ordinary experiences are all
similar in that they consist of various objects appearing to us. They are further
similar in that if we investigate the nature of these objects with sufficient
diligence, we will realize that the objects do not exist as solid entities, but
actually arise from the coming together of various causes. They are further similar
in that the objects that appear will withstand some limited modes of investigation.
It is only when we look carefully enough that we will see the limitations.
It's
like the Wizard of Oz. At first the great face and voice very definitely appeared,
created fear, and inspired obedience. Later, upon further investigation, it became
clear that the face and voice were merely appearing as the result of various circus
tricks and there was no substance to the appearance. Ordinary experience, scientific
experience, and dream experience are all similar in that they consist of various
objects appearing that will withstand some investigation but not all investigation.
These various types of experience differ in just what modes of investigation they
can withstand and what modes reveal their limitations. That's why what we experience
is called relative or conventional. In various situations we describe the world
relative to some conventional modes of investigation. Oftentimes confusion arises
when in a discussion two people are working with different conventions.
Experience
has far more varieties than just the three of ordinary, scientific, and dream.
These three themselves are just very coarse groupings. Consider rainbows. Do rainbows
really exist? In some ways yes, in some ways no. Unlike dreams, many people can
see the same rainbow at the same time. You can even take a photograph of a rainbow.
One doesn't wake up from seeing a rainbow to the sound of the alarm clock buzzing,
unless of course it was a dream rainbow! But if you try to grab a rainbow, you
can never find anything to hold on to. Rainbows actually have no definite location;
they have a direction, but no distance.
Lightning is another classical object
of experience whose mode of existence can be contemplated. What is amazing about
lightning is the contrast between the intense presence of its existence with its
miniscule duration. By the time one can even formulate the idea of the existence
of the flash of lightning, the lightning is already gone.
Consider the phenomenon
of seeing stars when one is struck in the head. The stars most certainly do appear.
Yet no one else in the room can see them, at least not right then. But others
will likely have seen similar stars at other times, when they themselves had been
struck in the head. Here is a curious variation on the theme of intersubjective
experience!
"Did you watch the president give his speech last night?"
If I watched a flickering image of the president projected on a phosphor screen
by an scanning electron beam, I will still likely answer, "Yes!" What
I saw and heard was not the actual president, but merely an illusion projected
by electronic circuitry. Many other people saw the same or similar images. The
next day I can talk with my coworkers about the phenomena that appeared, and we
will all have had very similar experiences. Yet if I shout out a question or an
objection or try to tweak the president's nose, I will certainly discover that
there is no person actually present.
Some experiences we just stumble upon,
other experiences we have to work to achieve. To watch TV, we might have to go
out and buy a TV and then plug it in and turn in on and find a channel that works.
Or maybe we have to get a cable hookup activated.
I am always amazed to reflect
that of the three famous papers Einstein published in 1905, it was the paper on
Brownian motion that won him the Nobel prize. (The other papers were on the photoelectric
effect and on special relativity.) Still in 1905 it was controversial as to whether
or not atoms and molecules actually existed or were just a convenient fiction
for explaining the regularities of chemical combinations. Einstein used Brownian
motion to measure the size of molecules, thus settling the controversy in favor
of their actual existence. Nowadays we have scanning tunneling electron microscopes
that can generate clear images of arrangements of individual atoms! We generally
take the existence of atoms for granted, but it took the work of many genius scientists
to build up the equipment required to make atoms clearly appear as existing objects.
Geiger and Rutherford exposed the internal structure of the atom, revealing electrons
and nuclei and the vast empty spaces that constitute atoms. The history of microphysics
in the twentieth century is a continuing sequence of ever new modes of investigation
revealing the limited nature of the existence of one class of objects by making
apparent how those objects are built up from arrangements and interactions of
yet finer objects.
Each scientific discipline has its own conventional methods
of investigation and its own objects that appear through the application of those
methods. What appears for a zoologist to be a horse looks for a chemist to be
a system of interlocked chemical reaction processes and for a physicist to be
a configuration of particles coursing along trajectories determined by fundemental
force field equations. An economist might see an investment with certain anticipated
risk and return!
If we investigate a phenomenon closely enough, then we will
discover that the objects that appeared are really just limited rough approximations
to the real facts, facts that incorporate a whole range of deeper phenomena that
came into focus as the investigation unfolded and that together explained how
the phenomenon came into appearance. Yet at the same time that we can understand
and reflect upon the limited nature of the existence of whatever objects might
appear to us, still when phenomena appear, they do truly appear. In one sense
a rainbow does not really exist but is merely an appearance generated by light
and mist. In another sense, a rainbow most certainly exists as a circular pattern
of brightly colored stripes. All phenomena have this twofold nature. Ultimately
one can always investigate deeply enough to reveal what is behind an appearance
and the limitations of that appearance. But apart from those investigations and
within those limitations, phenomena do arise and appear.
Breaking
and Fixing
We have examined a variety of ways to describe the world and discussed
the problems that prevent a precise fit between world and description. Given the
boundless ingenuity and passion of humanity, one can reasonably anticipate that
every problem that arises will eventually be repaired. The difficulty seems to
be that every repair introduces additional complexity and abstraction into the
description, introducing new and even more difficult problems. It's like the mythological
hydra, where seven new heads grow in place of every head one chops off. Must new
problems always arise, or might there be an end to the process, at which point
a perfect description will have been reached?
It appears impossible, even
absurd, to construct a proof that problems must always arise for any description.
Any such proof would rely on some description for its terms, axioms, and inferences.
The ultimate validity of the proof would depend on the ultimate validity of the
underlying description. But the proposition to be proved is that no such ultimately
valid description is possible! This is remarkably close to Goedel's proposition,
which he constructed to demonstrate that there are true propositions of arithmetic
that cannot be proved. To the extent that any correct description of the world
must inevitably incorporate arithmetic, and to the extent that Goedel's incompleteness
theorem indicates an inevitable flaw in any theory of arithmetic, we can construct
an argument that any description of the world can fit only imprecisely. But the
dynamics of problems and patches continues in the contemporary debates on the
philosophy of mathematics and competing interpretations of Goedel's theorem. It
is enough for our purposes to note that in the realm of mathematics, the debates
continue: the descriptions proposed in the last round had their problems discovered;
it seems overly optimistic to suppose that the current round of patches will finally
resolve all problems.
This dynamic structure of problems and patches seems
to be fundamental. One party insists that truth exists and advocates law and order
to respect that truth. The other party points out the contrived nature of the
proposed law and order and proposes free and creative improvisation in its place.
These are the extreme positions of eternalism and nihilism, of objectivism and
relativism. The objectivist holds that when you push an investigation far enough,
in the end you get down to solid fixed reality, the ultimate cold hard facts of
the matter. The relativist holds that when you push an investigation far enough,
in the end you get to a set of arbitrary free choices which could just as well
have been chosen otherwise.
Buddhism resolves the dispute with a Middle Way.
No matter how far you push an investigation, you can always push it further. At
each stage of investigation one is confronted with some set of phenomena that
are discovered to underlie more superficial appearances. But these phenomena themselves
can be investigated in turn, uncovering yet deeper structures, patterns, and interconnections.
Aristotle traced the causal chain back to a starting point, back to the prime
mover. The Christian tradition mapped the prime mover onto God. Buddhism is atheistic,
in contrast. There is no prime mover. The causal chain can be traced back ever
more deeply in beginningless time.
This is the deep truth of Buddhism, emptiness
and interdependence as two ways to say the same thing. Phenomena are never ultimate,
neither in the eternalist objectivist version of fixed absolute forms, nor in
the nihilist relativist version of freely chosen forms. Whatever phenomena arise,
those phenomena are always subject to further investigation which would reveal
those phenomena to be emergent patterns dependent on a network of relationships
with various other supporting or underlying phenomena. This is the endless dynamic
of the problems and patches of descriptions. A description records uninvestigated
arising phenomena. Further investigation reveals problems that inevitably plague
any such description. Patches fix the problems by rewriting the description in
terms of deeper, underlying phenomena.
The Seventeenth Century founders of
the modern scientific tradition were deeply religious Christian thinkers. They
viewed their study of nature as a reading of a second Bible revealed by God, the
Book of Nature. Their faith in the existence of an ultimately valid description
was a part of their faith in God. Modern science, to the extent that it retains
this faith in ultimately valid description, is thus a Christian science, or at
least adheres to the family of the monotheistic Religions of the Book, of Judaism,
Christianity, and Islam. Given such a religious foundation for science, the possibility
of an alternative science, a science with a different metaphysical foundation,
becomes more clear.
Methods
and Results
The blossoming of science in the 1600's was rooted in the reawakening
of a skeptical outlook in the 1500's with Agrippa, Rabelais, and Montaigne, leading
to Descartes. This philosophical questioning was mirrored in the social, religious,
and political instabilities of the time. This skeptical outlook was not new -
Pyrrho, Aristotle's nephew, had promulgated similar views, inspired by his meetings
with thinkers in India during his travels with Alexander's armies. One could even
consider science to be a product of Buddhist influence in Europe!
The heart
of skepticism, which is also cental to Buddhist philosophy, is that things are
not what they seem. We build our lives up based on our beliefs, what we take to
be true. We are often then confronted with unpleasant surprises. What we took
to be true turns out to be false. Our world collapses when the foundations we
have relied upon reveal their instability.
Uncertainty in our convictions
can also arise when we discover that other people have different beliefs than
we do. Before we discover that our own beliefs are unreliable, we tend to quickly
conclude that other people's conflicting beliefs must simply be wrong. It often
seems justified to apply any means necessary to eliminate such error so truth
may prevail. Heretics are burned, religious wars mounted.
With sufficient
maturity a more skeptical attitude may develop. One learns through experience
that one's own beliefs are not reliable, that just because one believes a thing
does not imply the truth of that belief. Even if one has tested a belief, further
experience may shake that belief, may reveal some deeper truth, may awaken one
to one's illusions. When one confronts a conflicting belief, one realizes that
one's own belief could actually be the one in error. Instead of just assuming
that one's own beliefs must be the true ones, instead one initiates a process
of investigation, gathering and weighing evidence, engaging in debate and negotiation.
One suspends commitment to one's own beliefs at least temporarily, attempting
to judge impartially between conflicting beliefs based on the facts rather than
the vagaries of historically entrenched opinion.
With such an approach one
has shifted the ground of one's faith from a particular set of beliefs to a method
of deciding among beliefs. The scientific method is just this, a commitment to
deciding belief though a process of gathering evidence and weighing it through
public discourse. As science developed in European culture, so did parallel notions
of deciding political issues by democratic processes and economic issues by market
processes. This commitment to investigate beliefs we can call "first-order
skepticism". The facts about the way the world works, or the value of a commodity,
or the social behavior should be regulated, are to be decided by processes of
negotiation and debate rather than by any fixed rule eternally etched in the stone
of traditional authority.
To question the results of such processes of public
negotiation and debate, to propose an alternative science, might seem like a proposal
to return to some such fixed authority. Indeed such authoritarian alternatives
have not only been proposed but enacted in fundamentalist and totalitarian regimes
where debate and negotiation are ruthlessly suppressed.
But in fact there
are many possible methods of gathering and weighing evidence, many possible decision
procedures. To consider alternatives to one method is not to reject all methods
but to start opening up to this space of possibility. The traditional forms of
debate and negotiation are not the only forms. Alternative forms can be considered.
The advantages and disadvantages of the various forms can be investigated. We
can learn to apply more effective methods to decide between conflicting beliefs.
This questioning of method we can call "second-order skepticism".
With first-order skepticism we realized the possible truth of alternative beliefs.
With second-order skepticism we realize the potential value of alternative methods
of investigation, of gathering and weighing evidence, of debate and negotiation.
The traditional methods may not lead to the best decisions. We recognize the need
to investigate the methods themselves.
This investigation of alternative methods
is already bearing fruit in politics and economics. The superiority in some political
situations of various voting methods such as approval voting have been demonstrated.
Various forms of bidding have been explored and their improved efficiency demonstrated
in some market situations. But how to investigate methods of investigation? Doesn't
the circularity, the paradoxicality of such a project doom it, render it fruitless
or impossible or meaningless? This obstacle seems to be rooted in Cartesian dualism,
the adherence to a clean division between the knowing subject and the known object.
From such a dualistic perspective, it cannot be impossible for the process of
knowing to itself be an object of knowing. Second-order skepticism lets go of
this dualism. However we go about investigating methods of investigation, the
way we go about it may become itself an object of investigation. Here again we
may call on our faith in Buddhism to give us courage to devote ourselves to compassionate
action within a vast space without fixed reference points. It is the clinging
to beliefs and institutions as if they were eternal and absolute, the refusal
to recognize their conventionality, the refusal to investigate their interdependence,
that creates suffering.
Chaos
and Friction in Theory Evolution
Our theories about the world are a part of
the world. The dynamic evolution of the world includes the dynamic evolution of
our theories about the world. The "standard modern" picture of the pattern
of the evolution of theories is that, at least once the world-system has crossed
over into the scientific attractor basin, that theories gradually and steadily
approach some fixed point. This fixed point can serve as an effective notion of
truth. Perhaps my main theme in this essay is that this picture of the dynamic
evolution of theories is an inadequate picture. As an analogy, in the past the
standard model for thermodynamic systems was an isolated system gradually approaching
equilibrium. Since at least the 1960's, scientists have been exploring the behavior
of open systems and systems far from equilibrium. It looks now like the isolated
system gradually approaching equilibrium is very much a special case.
What
is the actual pattern of the dynamic evolution of scientific theories? The question
is not exactly historical. It is not a matter of the path that science actually
takes, but of all the various paths it might take. If in fact all paths eventually
settle within some small neighborhood of a single fixed point, then this fixed
point could well serve as truth. But if the various possible trajectories of theory
evolution actually wander into very diverse regions, then the question of truth
gets more complicated. Perhaps one trajectory indeed settles for a very long time
in one neighborhood, and a different trajectory also settles in a neighborhood,
but the two neighborhoods are very different. The modern theories of chaotic dynamics
have charted out an amazing menagerie of patterns of trajectories.
What I
propose is that the actual dynamics of theory evolution is chaotic. Proving this
to be true may be very difficult, impossible, or paradoxical. Wouldn't any purported
proof need to hold itself up as some sort of universal fixed point in a dynamic
space of theories about theories, which as part of the actual evolution of the
entire world is coupled into the dynamics of the first order theory evolution
and therefore subject to the chaos that it intends merely to be about rather than
itself subjected to?
Here we have two competing theories. The standard modern
philosophy of science holds that the dynamic system of theory evolution is non-chaotic,
that essentially the entire space of theories constitutes one big basin of attraction
with a simple fixed point. The alternative proposed here (and by many others)
is that the dynamic system of theory evolution is chaotic, with the full panorama
of attractor types etc. How can we decide which of these theories is better?
In
my discussions on this subject, one friend proposed that since the standard modern
philosophy of science is the established dominant view, the burden of proof is
on the newcomer chaotic theory. It occurs to me that this argument puts a very
nice wrinkle into the problem. This wrinkle relies on a feature of general system
dynamics. Static friction leads to chaos! When a system wants to stay where it
is and resists movement, that tendency leads to multiple basins of attraction.
This observation doesn't prove that theory evolution is indeed chaotic, but it
does encourage an examination of the issue based on the merits of the different
positions rather than the history of the power of their various advocates. Arguing
for the standard view on the basis of its standardness undermines that very view
itself!
A Middle Way for Science
The
alternative science I am proposing is not a replacement of the current scientific
description of the world with some new description. Scientists are constantly
proposing new alternative descriptions, weighing and debating the merits of the
various competing proposals, inventing and performing experiments to gather evidence
to help tilt the balance. That's what science is about.
I am proposing a new
understanding of what science is, which should lead to a new way of doing science.
Buddhism has cultivated the seed of the basic truth of emptiness and interdependence,
and harvested a rich tradition of 2500 years of international culture. How can
the wisdom of Buddhism transform science?
There is not likely to be an absolute
universal ultimate answer at this level either, but rather an ongoing process
of reflective practise. Some starting principles could be:
" How we do
science matters. There is no inevitable progress to some unique final result.
Every description has limitations, distortions, and blind spots. These form a
sort of hidden historical record of the unresolved conflicts accumulated in the
process of constructing the description.
" The value of a scientific
description is in its ability to help beings become free from suffering and acheive
their highest potential.
" Scientific descriptions are always embedded
in contexts of people, equipment, materials, etc.
" Science like any
human activity has a mythological narrative dimension. For example, a scientist
might consciously or unconsciouly imagine himself or herself as a knight crusader
in shining armor fighting valiantly to protect truth from the onslaught of the
heretics. Acknowledging and working with this mythological dimension may be a
wiser way to manage its powerful energies than trying to suppress and deny it.
" The mythological narrative of science encompasses a vision of humanity
and its place in the universe, not just the institutions of science itself. Science
fiction was born together with science, in works such as Francis Bacon's New Atlantis.
The direction of evolution of science and technology seem inevitable largely because
of the lack of consciousness and acknowledgement of this mythological narrative.
Acting and Accepting
In
conceptualizing our experience we generally classify things in terms of polar
opposites, such as hot versus cold, light versus dark, good versus bad, etc. Often
we line up these opposites in rows under the two master column headings of good
and bad, perhaps something like:
good
bad
pleasure pain
rich poor
sweet
bitter
... ...
As we mature and reflect on our broadening experience, we
may begin to question how we have lined up one or more of these opposites. Perhaps
our taste changes, and instead of savoring sweet desserts, we start to search
out the hottest chilis and curries. Changing food preferences rarely represent
profound life changes - though perhaps if our perspective on thick juicy steaks
changes it might seem relatively profound. A more significant pair of opposites
for living life is the choice between accepting things as they are versus acting
to change them. We might grow up holding one approach to be superior, then perhaps
in mid-life re-evaluate the options and decide that the other alternative is actually
superior, and so we work to change our habitual approach.
With more experience
and reflection, our attitude about pairs of opposites can continue to evolve.
We can start to see that perhaps neither extreme is optimal, that in fact some
third middle way is the best. We might come to realize that no fixed approach
will always be the best, rather we must examine each situation and apply the approach
that is appropriate to the particular circumstances. When we reach this stage
with the poles of acting and accepting, we understand Reinhold Niebuhr's famous
prayer for serenity, courage, and wisdom.
Eventually, by looking carefully
at the nature of opposites, we might realize that each pole actually incorporates
its opposite, one way or another, as an essential component. Effective action
is only possible when we accept the way the world is so that we can work with
it. Airplanes free us from the speed limits imposed by older modes of transportation,
and in that sense represent a refusal to accept such limitation. On the other
hand, airplanes only became possible when the Wright brothers built a wind tunnel
to study aerodynamics and understand how the shape of its wings affect the behavior
of an airplane. Without accepting the laws of aerodynamics, airplanes would be
impossible. Similarly, acceptance is not possible without action. For example,
genuine acceptance of new neighbors into a community might require some action,
such as offering a concrete token of welcome.
The cartoon images of traditional
Buddhism and modern Science seem to line up with the polar opposites of accepting
and acting. Modern European-American culture has certainly used science and technology
to take action on grand scales in many arenas. My own life is thoroughly enveloped
in this culture, so I don't really have enough first hand experience on which
to base any characterization of traditional Buddhist culture. Certainly the grand
temples of Buddhist Asia give evidence of significant activity. But still, in
traditional cultures around the world, including pre-modern Europe, it seems there
is a greater acceptance of circumstance. The modern notion of progress seems to
generate a boundless optimism which can support and motivate grand activity, while
the traditional notion of degeneration from an earlier golden age seems to lead
to a more pessimistic and less active approach.
Thinking about this further,
maybe the situation is a bit more complex. Presented with some unpleasant circumstance,
a Buddhist might reflect that it is really a bit over-optimistic to think that
any amount of activity could actually eliminate unpleasant circumstances from
the world. But this doesn't mean that there is nothing to be done. Instead of
avoiding the pain of stepping on thorns and pebbles by paving the entire planet
with a smooth and soft surface, one can instead put on shoes. The space of activity
can be internal instead of external. Changing one's habitual patterns of thought
and emotion is a project requiring as much persistence and effort as any material
engineering project. In contrast, the modern way is not to question one's desires.
The mark of privilege is indulging one's impulses. We seem to have arrived at
a more complex relationship among these polarities:
traditional Buddhism
modern Science
internal
external internal
external
act accept accept
act
Perhaps we can look yet deeper at the contrast between traditional Buddhism
and modern Science. Just as sustained reflection on the natures of acting and
accepting led to the realization that each pole relies on its opposite, similarly
we might look to see whether or how the traditional Buddhist approach and the
modern Scientific approach are mutually interdependent.
How does a traditional
Buddhist approach rely on a modern Scientific approach? The essence of Buddhism
is benefitting others. The only way to accomplish this benefit is by a penetrating
understanding of the nature of reality, together with precise and courageous performance
of the actions required. This is science and technology at its best.
How does
a modern Scientific approach rely on a traditional Buddhist approach? The essence
of Science is communal inquiry. The only way to accomplish this is to insure that
all members of the broadest community have the maximum opportunity to extend the
depth and range of their insights and to freely share and help each other grow.
This is Buddhism at its best!
Beyond
Civilization
I recently read Thom Hartmann's The Last Hours of Ancient Sunlight:
Waking Up To Personal and Global Transformation (Three Rivers, 1999). It's pretty
thorough on the ecological scare tactics front! A related subject I've been researching
a bit lately is solar power. A recent article in Science talked about generating
all the power for the US from 10,000 square miles of solar collectors in Nevada.
Not really a serious proposal, but it points out a possibility. I found another
report on-line, a KPMG study done for Greenpeace that discussed large scale solar
electric power. Right now electricity from solar panels runs about 10x the cost
from the power company, depending no doubt on where you are. I wonder how the
numbers would work out in say San Diego these days?! The biggest problem seems
to be that the manufacturing capacity isn't there. Everything these days runs
on economies of scale. Well maybe not everything, I guess mini-mills are big in
steel these days. But anyway, the KPMG report talks about a chicken-and-egg problem,
that nobody will build a big enough factory to get the unit cost down until the
demand is there, but the demand won't be there until the cost comes down.
It's
a very interesting question: if some social structure or pattern of behavior A
is more optimal in some sense than pattern B, will society somehow inevitably
evolve into pattern A before too long, before pattern A becomes non-optimal because
of changes in circumstances? The Whig history approach is just to say, whatever
pattern we have must be optimal just because we have it, its existence is proof
of its optimality, and who anyway can justify any sort of lofty authority to make
any other judgements of optimality anyway? Well that isn't my approach at all,
I think we each of us have the fundamental responsibility as human beings to take
responsibility and make judgements and act as wisely as possible to improve things
one way or another. I view the general pattern of human society to be miserably
sub-optimal and given all the various feedback loops that amplify stupidity and
desparation, I don't see any very big opportunities for improvement! But the space
of possibilities includes wonderful and delightful feedback loops of bliss and
wisdom, and maybe all we need is a small opportunity after all with a few of the
right nudges in the right place! Anything is possible!
I don't really see
how we can get solar power in place before oil starts to collapse. But there's
lots of coal, so the real race is with global warming. Then there's nuclear. It
seems like we'll poison ourselves one way or another before we run out of raw
materials. The chain of cause and effect is so long, how can people become aware
of the link between their behavior and the consequences they experience, or that
their grandchildren will experience?
For me the weakest part of Hartmann's
book is the vision. He seems stuck proposing a return to tribal life, pre-civilization.
I have a different vision. I don't mind seeing the issue on the table coming out
of the tribal - civilization transition. A real strength of Hartmann's book is
that he shows how big civilized empires emerged out of tribal life at multiple
times in multiple places. At one point he does though paint a picture of some
evil being who poisons things, as if civilization doesn't emerge as much as get
introduced from some sort of outside influence. This I view as a deeply flawed
vision. Hartmann likes to contrast sustainable tribal culture with unsustainable
civilized culture, cataloging the many collapses of the many great civilizations
that have risen and fallen over the millenia. But this isn't quite right. Tribal
culture is not sustainable either! The collapse of civilized culture is generally
due to some resource limit or plague. Tribal culture reveals its instability when
somehow it evolves into civilization!
So my grand vision is of some kind of
trans-civilization, some kind of culture that goes past civilization. This echoes
all the post-modern blather, but trumps it. Forget the puny little medieval -
modern transition, let's go deeper, to the tribal - civilized transition! One
can look at the history of civilization as one of bigger and bigger empires forming
and collapsing. Finally now we are entering into the grandest civilization yet,
the global city. No more frontier! And at the same time, we're on the cusp of
the grandest collapse yet. Of course, anybody's guess how all this plays out.
But if we cultivate a vision of the most positive possibilities, perhaps the right
little incalculable nudges will somehow carry us through the narrowest window
of opportunity.
My notion of trans-civilization is built on Ken Wilber's concept
of the pre-trans fallacy. He's talking about ego, how enlightenment (in the yogic
sense) is not any sort of infantile regression to a pre-egoic state, but a further
evolution to a trans-egoic state, one that must incorporate elements of ego as
it becomes free of the limitations of ego. Similarly, a trans-civilized culture
will have to incorporate elements of civilization but at the same time recovering
some elements of tribal life, just as the enlightened master recovers some of
the innocence and spontaneity of a child.
Resources
for Philosophy
John D. Caputo
" Deconstruction in a Nutshell: A Conversation
with Jacques Derrida, Fordham 1997
This is probably the only book where I've
managed to read more than a page of Derrida's writing. The first 24 pages are
the transcript of a Q&A with Derrida. The rest is a commentary by Caputo.
It sure does seem like there is some resonance here with Buddhism, which other
have also noted. Anyway, try the following mapping:
" khora = emptiness
" differance = interdependence
" Messiah = Buddha nature
Perhaps
a significant difference with Buddhism is that the Messiah is always projected
into the future, whereas Buddha nature is always already present though obscure.
Fred Dallmayr
" Beyond Orientalism: Essays on Cross-Cultural Encounter,
(SUNY 1996)
from p. 195:
The conception of democratic staging as an empty
place resonates deeply with the Buddhist notion of sunyata (as outlined above).
As in the case of Buddhism, democratic emptiness does not denote nihilism or sheer
negativity but rather a kind of inner lining or hidden foil allowing democratic
politics to emerge in its suchness. If sunyata is seen as a core ingredient of
Buddhism (at least in its Mahayana version), then contemporary politics offers
the spectacle of a curious East-West encounter: just at the time when Western-style
democracy is experiencing a worldwide affirmation allowing us to speak of a process
of global democratization, democratic politics discovers in itself a non-actuality
or hidden hollow, a hollow whose understanding can be greatly assisted by the
rich Buddhist legacy of sunyata.
John Dewey
" The Quest for Certainty:
A Study of the Relation of Knowledge and Action (Putnam 1929)
from pp. 104-105
Only when the older theory of knowledge and epistemology is retained, is science
thought to inform us that nature in its true reality is but an interplay of masses
in motion, without sound, color, or any quality of enjoyment and use. What science
actually does is to show that any natural object we please may be treated in terms
of relations upon which its occurence depends, or as an event, and that by so
treating it we are enabled to get behind, as it were, the immediate qualities
the object of direct experience presents, and to regulate their happening, instead
of having to wait for conditions beyond our control to bring it about. Reduction
of experienced objects to the form of relations, which are neutral as respects
qualitative traits, is a prerequisite of ability to regulate the course of change,
so that it may terminate in the occurence of an object having desired qualities.
from p. 215:
Intelligence within nature means liberation and expansion,
as reason outside nature means fixation and restriction.
Richard King
"
Orientalism and Religion: Postcolonial Theory, India and 'The Mystic East' (Routledge
1999)
from p. 28:
It has become commonplace in the modern era to consider
mystics, their writings and the phenomenon of mysticism in general as being in
some sense antithetical to rationality. Specifically the characterization of Indian
religions such as Hinduism and Buddhism as mystical has also tended to support
the exclusion of Hindus and Buddhists from the realm of rationality.
David
Michael Levin
" The Body's Recollection of Being: Phenomenolgical Psychology
and the Deconstruction of Nihilism, (Routledge Kegan Paul 1985)
from p. 230:
Our traditional way of teaching morality is, I think, an inherently mechanizing,
technologically willfull way: it attempts to teach a morality of autonomy, but
does so by implicitly heteronomous means, i.e., by imposing precepts and principles
not derived from the child's own body of morally perceptive feeling, and by addressing
moral education to the child's tool-like nature, rather than to a creative reserve
of sensibility which is not reducible to its being as an instrument of moral culture,
and which may suffer very seriously from the instrumental strategy. When precepts
are imposed and not derived, it is not only that we betray our own principles
by treating the child as a tool, but that, since we are giving him no understanding
of moral evaluation as a process of articulating a body of implicitly moral feeling,
we are actually encouraging and rewarding a tool-like nature, rigid, constant,
reliable, fixed, docile, and essectially reactive, rather than thoughtful and
responsive. This educational method is therefore implicitly technological, and
tends to reproduce itself in a character which is easily manipulated, and which
knows by example only those kinds of relationship that involve the manipulation
of others. We desparately need a method of moral education which will avoid the
chains of calculative ratiocination and subvert the technological reduction of
human nature and comportment.
" The Listening Self: Personal Growth,
Social Change and the Closure of Metaphysics
" The Opening of Vision:
Nihilism and the Postmodern Situation
David Loy
" Lack and Transcendence:
The Problem of Death and Life in Psy
" Nonduality: A Study in Comparative
Philosophy
Robert Magliola
" Derrida on the Mend, (1984 Purdue)
from
pp. 87-88:
At the very outset of this discussion, however, I wish to dispel
two vitiating suspicions - one suspicion which is rooted in a covert bigotry but
is nonetheless commonplace among Western intellectuals who are not Orientalists,...
The first suspicion would have it that the principles of Buddhist throught in
general are too 'escapist', too 'other worldly' in the perjerotive sense of the
term, too preposterously removed from the real, to be worthy of attention, and
consequently, that any comparison of Derrida and Nagarjuna can only result in
miscarriage; or, in a variation which is a little more generous, that Buddhist
thought is too alien to Western sensibilities, and on this count well nigh irrecuperable,
so that a putative comparison of these two thinkers is de facto meaningless. Let
me assure such supicious ones that Buddhist thought, and the Hindu thought which
chronologically precedes and accompanies it, are as spectacularly diverse and
profound and rigorous and challenging and indeed relevant as European thought;
that the activity of Greek pre-Socratic schools found their counterpart in the
intense metaphysical debates of the early and middle Upanishadic periods - that
Indian philosophy divided into materialist, evolutionist, atomistic, idealist,
and other schools; that Aristotelian and scholastic logic were matched by the
elaborate Indian Nyaya and he Chinese "canons of Mo Tzu"; and that the
Western medieval and renaissance periods were also tenures of breathtaking esthetic,
philosophic, and religious activity in the East. What is more, traditional Oriental
thought is experiencing revived and new growth in contemporary times, especially
in the non-Marxist Orient and in large part through fertile dialogue with Western
specialists: Chinese logicians with Gernman logicians, Indian philosophers with
American philosophers, Buddhist monks with Catholic monks, Japanese poets with
Brazilian poets, and so on.
" On Deconstructing Life-Worlds: Buddhism,
Christianity, Culture, (Scholars Press 1997)
Mary Midgley
" Wisdom,
Information and Wonder: What is Knowledge for? (Routledge 1989)
from p. 135
The metaphor of foundations has got quite out of hand here. It expresses the
notion that the items we can know can be arranged in a single, one-dimensional
series in order of their certainty. In this case, what we would have to do would
be to get them piled up in that order, resting the less certain always upon the
more certain to make the whole set form a pyramid. In order to manage this, we
would have first to find something intrinsically undoubtable to put at the bottom,
something both immovable and large enough to support the whole pyramid. Philosophers
have long noticed that Descartes's Cogito cannot really fill this place, and no
other likely candidate has ever been found. Indeed, it seems implicit in the gravitational
metaphor that none ever can be found, since there is no end to the progress that
is possible downwards.
from pp. 157-158
This mention of how the facts
sometimes seem to vary with the values does not tip us into helpless scepticism.
It simply calls attention to the unity of the moral enterprise, to the web of
conceptual links between all its various facets. The process of change could,
of course, be described just as well the other way round, in the form in which
it often appeared to those who underwent it, as a recognition of the fats which
entailed a rejection of slavery. What was happening was a single complex process
with three conceptually linked aspects: a changing view of the facts, a change
of feeling, and a change in action, arising out of a changed sense of what action
could be decently contemplated. It has been a real misfortune, not just for philosophy
but for our civilization itself, that philosophers in the tradition we are discussing
have tended to concentrate entirely on separating these factors and putting them
in competition with each other, rather than on investigating the relations between
them.
Barbara Herrnstein Smith
" B elief and Resistance: Dynamics
of Contemporary Intellectual Controversy, (Harvard 1997)
from p. 80:
It
appears (on the evidence of, among other things, alternative introspections) that
ideas such as "inescapable presuppositions," "intuitive preunderstanding,"
and "truth absolute" are neither universal nor inescapable. On the contrary,
it is possible to believe (as statements in this book testify) that such concepts
and the sense of their inherent meanings and deep interconnectedness are, rather,
the products and effects of rigorous instruction and routine participation in
a particular conceptual tradition and its related idiom. It is also possible to
believe, accordingly, that instruction (more or less rigorous) in some other conceptual
tradition, and familiarity with its idiom, would yield other conceptions and descriptions
of "the fundamental nature" of "thought itself" and of what
is "presupposed" by "the very act of assertion." Or, one might
say (in the alternative idiom of one such alternative tradition), different personal/professional
histories are likely to make different descriptions and accounts of the operations
of human cognition and communication appear coherent and adequate.
Joan Stambaugh
"
The Finitude of Being
" Formless Self
" Impermanence is Buddha-nature:
Dogen's Understanding of Temp
" The Real is Not the Rational, (SUNY 1986)
from p. 98:
Whereas in most Western philosophy, for example, in Descartes,
the point of departure and the method to reach the nature of reality are clearly
defined, i.e., to start with the res cogitans (thinking thing), prove the existence
of God, and finally regain some certainty about the outside world. Given his philosophical
enterprise of finding a fundamentum inconcussum (unshakeable foundation) for knowledge,
Descartes could not have proceeded any other way than he did. His method is discursive,
step by step, and analytical. In Buddhism, when there is a fundamental concept,
for example, suffering or pain (duhkha), all the essential concepts relative to
it manifest all at once. And if there is real understanding of the "access"
to reality, the reality itself is present.
Having stated these difficulties
at the outset, let us attempt to see where Buddhism "starts." Descartes
started with methodological doubt, and arrived at himself, at the thinking thing.
Buddhism starts with the Four Noble Truths, which involve neither a self nor thinking,
nor a thing. In the statement that life is suffering, the first of the Four Noble
Truths, we already have the other two fundamental statements running through any
form of Buddhism, be it Indian, Chinese or Japanese, that all is impermanent and
that there is no self. The fundamentum inconcussum of Buddhism is unshakable,
but, so to speak, unshakable the way an abyss is unshakable. You cannot "shake"
what you cannot take hold of. The "foundation" here is bottomless. The
only thing "foundational" about it is its absolute givenness. It is,
so to speak, a foundation which envelopes us, not something on which we can reach
the stability of a "stand".
Stanley Tambiah
" Magic, Science,
Religion, and the Scope of Rationality
Resources
for Knowledge
Chris Argyris
" Action Science, coauthored by Robert
Putnam and Diana McLain Smith. Jossey-Bass 1985.
" Knowledge for Action:
A Guide to Overcoming Barriers to Organizational Change, Jossey-Bass 1993.
Gregory
Bateson
" Steps to an Ecology of Mind, Chandler 1972.
" Mind
and Nature: A Necessary Unity, Dutton 1979.
" Angels Fear: Toward an
Epistemology of the Sacred, coauthored by Mary Catherine Bateson, 1987 Macmillan.
" A Sacred Unity: Further Steps to an Ecology of Mind, HarperCollins
1991, edited by Rodney E. Donaldson.
" A Recursive Vision: Ecological
Understanding and Gregory Bateson, by Peter Harries-Jones, Toronto 1995.
Alan
Combs
" Radiance of Being: Complexity, Chaos and the Evolution of Consciousness
Edward de Bono
" I Am Right - You Are Wrong: From Rock Logic to Water
Logic (Viking Penguin 1991)
" Parallel Thinking: From Socratic to de
Bono Thinking (Viking Penguin 1994)
from pp. 2-3
We can take the complacent
view that poverty, pollution, local wars and local chaos are the inevitable result
of change and of human nature. ... If, however, we were to have doubts about this
complacency (doubting complacency is a classic oxymoron) then we might get around
to asking ourselves threes possible questions:
10. Is it possible that some
of our troubles are actually caused by inadequate thinking habits?
11. Is
it possible that our difficulty, and sometimes inability, to put things right
is due to inadequate thinking methods?
12. Is it possible that better thinking
could make things better?
... The standard traditional Western thinking style
was set by the famous Greek Gang of Three: Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle. ...
In this book I intend to examine the adequacy of our hallowed thinking habits.
The purpose is not merely to criticize, which is an easy exercise of intellect,
but to suggest alternatives in those places where the traditional method seems
inadequate.
Kenneth J. Gergen
" Realities and Relationships: Soundings
in Social Construction, 1994 Harvard.
Susantha Goonatilake
" Evolution
of Information: Lineages in Gene, Culture and Artefact, (Pinter 1991)
from
p 126:
The information in a flow line is thus the encoding of past interactions
of the flow line directly or indirectly with the environment. This information
encodes a memory of past responses to the environment and is thereby a 'congealing
of past history'. The information can also be seen as a partial mapping of the
environment on to 'the flow lines'. The environment's current responses is always
potentially ahead of the already encoded aspects of the environment. The partial
coevolution of flow lines and environment is therefore by necessity potentially
out of step in time. ... If a sub-culture or group has internalized within its
members a wide variety of responses to the environment, this allows, in the event
of changes in the environment, a variety of possible responses. The historically
derived cultural elements of the flow lines are spread over a wide pool (as the
'common heritage' of the group, as past 'wisdom') and constitute a reservior of
possible responses.
" Toward a Global Science: Mining Civizational Knowledge
(Indiana 1998)
from p. 8:
If it sounds like I am accepting the "totalizing"
hegemony of modern science, I am. I want to enlarge it if possible, not destroy
it. I want to reach beyond the Enlightenment and the modern projects and some
of their Eurocentric limitations. But the modern sciences, when taken individually,
are not monolithic, ontologically and epistemologically totalizing projects. There
are too many differences and even contradictions in the approaches of the different
disciplines as to methodology, epistemology, and at times ontology. So science
as a totalizing project is totalizing only to the extent that it is an organized
skeptical attempt to gather valid knowledge. With that pursuit I am perfectly
comfortable. I want only to increase the skepticism, to make it more valid, and
to enlarge the catchment area.
Horst Hendriks-Jansen
" Catching Ourselves
in the Act: Situated Activity, Interactive Emergence, Evolution, and Human Thought,
MIT 1996.
Alicia Juarrero
" Dynamics in Action: Intentional Behavior
as a Complex System, MIT 1999
from p. 260:
We are enmeshed in a fabric
of time and space, which we unravel at our peril. In part, we are the product
of a complex dance between our innate endowments and an already structured physical
and social environment. We are never passive in this entire process, however.
Even the environment in which we are situated is itself, in part, the downstream
consequence of our own upstream doings, both phylogenetically and ontogenetically.
As such both culturally and individually, we bear a measure of responsibility
for that environment. Once we are mature and aware, we can self-consciously select
the stimuli to which we will respond and that will affect who we are in the future.
At that point we are as responsible for who we will become as is the environment.
And once again, this is true for each of us both as members of a community and
as individuals.
George Lakoff
" Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied
Mind and Its Challenge to Western Thought, coauthored by Mark Johnson. Basic Books
1999.
Peter M. Senge
" The Fifth Discipline : The Art and Practice
of the Learning Organization
Francisco Varela
" Autopoiesis and Cognition:
The Realization of the Living
" The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science
and Human Experience
" Principles of Biological Autonomy
" Tree
of Knowledge: The Biological Roots of Human Understanding, (Shambhala 1987), coauthored
by Humberto R. Maturana
from pp. 25-27:
Therefore, underlying everything
we shall say is this constant awareness that the phenomenon of knowing cannot
be taken as though there were "facts" or objects out there that we grasp
and store in our head. The experience of anything out there is validated in a
special way by the human structure, which makes possible "the thing"
that arises in the description.
This circularity, this connection between
action and experience, this inseparability between a particular way of being and
how the world appears to us, tells us that every act of knowing brings forth a
world. ... All doing is knowing, and all knowing is doing.
... Every reflection,
including one on the foundation of human knowledge, invariably takes place in
language, which is our distinctive way of being human and being humanly active.
For this reason, language is also our starting point, our cognitive instrument,
and our sticking point. ... Everything said is said by someone. Every reflection
brings forth a world. As such, it is a human action by someone in particular in
a particular place.
...
This bringing forth of knowledge is commonly regarded
as a stumbling block, an error or explanatory residue to be eradicated. This is
why, for instance, a colored shadow is said to be an "optical illusion"
and why "in reality" there s no color. What we are saying is exactly
the opposite: this characteristic of knowledge is the master key to understanding
it, not an annoying residue or obstacle.
" Ethical Know-How: Action,
Wisdom, and Cognition (Stanford 1999)
Georg von Krogh
" Organizational
Epistemology, coauthored by Johan Roos, St. Martins 1995.
Paul Watzlawick
"
Pragmatics of Human Communication: A Study of Interactional Patterns, Pathologies,
and Paradoxes, coauthored by Janet Beavin Bavelas and Don D. Jackson, 1967 Norton.
" How Real is Real: Confusion, Disinformation, Communication, 1976 Random
House.
" The Language of Change: Elements of Therapeutic Communication,
1978 Norton.
" The Situation is Hopeless, But Not Serious: The Pursuit
of Unhappiness, 1983 Norton.
" The Invented Reality: How Do We Know What
We Believe We Know? (Contributions to Constructivism), 1984 Norton.
A collection
of essays:
" "An Introduction to Radical Constructivism", Ernst
von Glasersfeld.
" "On Constructing a Reality", Heinz von Foerster.
" "The Consequences of Causal Thinking", Rupert Riedl.
"
"Self-Fulfilling Prophecies", Paul Watzlawick.
" "On Being
Sane in Insane Places", David L. Rosenhan.
" "Self-Reflexivity
in Literature: The Example of Samuel Beckett's Novel Trilogy", Rolf Breuer.
" "Active and Passive Negation: An Essay in Ibanskian Sociology",
Jon Elster.
" "Components of Ideological 'Realities'", Paul
Watzlawick.
" "Can an Inquiry into the Foundations of Mathematics
Tell Us Anything Interesting about Mind?", Gabriel Stolzenberg.
"
"The Creative Circle: Sketches on the Natural History of Circularity",
Francisco J. Varela.
" Münchhausen's Pigtail, or: Psychotherapy
and "Reality": Essays and Lectures, 1990 Norton
Etienne Wenger
"
Communities of Practise: Learning, Meaning, and Identity, Cambridge 1998.
Margaret
J. Wheatley
" a simpler way, (Berrett-Koehler 1996), coauthored by Myron
Kellner-Rogers
from p. 13:
It is the ability to keep finding solutions
that is important; any one solution is temporary. There are no permanently right
answers. The capacity to keep changing, to find what works now, is what keeps
any organism alive.
from p. 14:
Identity is the filter that every organism
or system uses to make sense of the world. New information, new relationships,
changing environments - all are interpreted through a sense of self. This tendency
toward self-creation is so strong that it creates a seeming paradox. An organism
will change to maintain its identity.
Randall Whitaker
" Self-Organization,
Autopoesis, and Enterprises
Resources
for Science
Sunny Y. Auyang
" How is Quantum Field Theory Possible?
(Oxford 1995)
from p. 113:
We have large areas of knowledge that are relatively
thorough so that each area can be regarded as a large content. We can envision
the development of the disciplinary sciences as attaining higher grounds and gaining
wider views. However, no matter how high we climb and how sweeping the vista is,
the view is always bounded by a horizon. The observed is a formal distinction
that signifies the horizon of knowledge, which can be realized in any way physical
theories see fit. As "I think" accompanies all my experiences, "we
think" formally accompanies all our knowledge. Finitude is a human condition
that cannot be obliterated by science. Perhaps we can broaden our horizon to include
the physical interaction between quantum and classical objects, but we can never
step out of our horizon to attain God's position.
from p. 192:
We have
seen in section 27 that individuals must have relational properties if they are
to relate to one another. The renormalization program demonstrates again that
reliability depends on definite presuppositions. Individuals in isolation are
different from individuals in a community; the former must be enriched with relatability
to become the latter. The free electron is free only within the electron-electromagnetic
field system, in which it is obliged by its own characteristics to relate causally
with other electrons and the elctromagnetic field. As for the absolutely isolated
and unrelatable electron, it turns out to be a ill-defined fiction.
from pp.
194-195:
Some philosophies assert that knowledge must be founded upon primitive
elements that have no conceptual complexity, for these elements are given, certain,
and free from theories. The role of theories is merely to organize the given elements
for more efficient reckoning. We have found in our investigation that every notion
they deem given is conceptually analyzable. One common assumption they make is
that the world consists of preindivduated entities that constitute the domain
of discourse, over which the variables of theories range. This assumption is shown
to be dubious in quantum field theory, in which individuation of events is a major
theoretical task that is achieved only with the concepts of space-time and private
state spaces. The result of individuation, not the givenness of the entities,
enables us to comprehend the world as comprising discrete events. Consequently
the concept of individual entities is complex and incorporates intrinsic spatio-temporal
notions. The concepts of properties and relations are equally analyzable. Even
the basic relations of similarity and difference have important presuppositions
that are tied to the concepts of enduring things and causality.
Henry H. Bauer
"
Scientific Literacy and the Myth of the Scientific Method, (Illinois 1992)
from
p. 61:
The myth of the method is not easily discarded, for one thing, because
humankind is reluctant to accept that all knowledge contains an irreducible, inherent
elemnt of uncertainty. Over the last few centruries, the authority of science
came to supersede that of religion precisely because science seemed to offer more
certain knowledge, at least about the tangible world. If scientific knowledge
now turns out to harbor ineradicable uncertainties, then science is in essence
a false god, and, moreover, is inferior to the God on whom science turned its
back. Human beings, after all, do want to be certain about fundamental things,
and religion offers (or used to offer) such certainty. So there is reluctance
to accept that the method is a myth, reluctance especially on the part of atheists,
secular humanists, Marxists, and other such ideologues - perhaps the more so because
fundamentalists and New Age obscurantists have also been so eager to topple science
from its pedestal of authoritative certainty.
Jack Cohen
" The Collapse
of Chaos: Discovering Simplicity in a Complex World, (Penguin 1994) coauthored
by Ian Stewart,
from 428-429:
This bears on a major question, which we
asked right at the start of the book and have not yet fully answered. Are the
patterns we perceive in nature real, or are they figments of our imaginations?
In The Mind's Sky Timothy Ferris uses the hourglass as an image of matter/mind:
The upper half of the glass is the material universe, the lower half is a human
mind, and the sand tricling from one to the other is information from the material
world entering the brain. But, as the story of Newton's ears shows, that image
is far too symmetric; it puts the mind's view of the universe on an equal footing
with the universe's view of the mind. Now, the sand inside the mind is indeed
a model of the material world, and it is that model that we manipulate when we
seek patterns. The material world is not part of our minds. But our minds are
part of the material world. The lower half of the hourglass is inside the upper
half (but not vice versa). A better image might be the mathematician's Klein bottle
which not only bends the lower half of the hourglass inside the upper, but does
so in such a way that the combined sureface has only one side. The "mind"
half is turned inside out, so that its contents are not directly identified with
any of the contents of the material half.
This image emphasizes the fact that
mind is a strange loop. "Information" about the material world can get
into our minds by routes that do not pass through our sense organs. If somebody
hits you on the head with a hammer and kills you, soe rather nasty information
about the material world has had a direct and major effect on your mind, by destroying
it. Hallucinogenic drugs affect the mind through its chemistry but create images
that seem to have come from sense organs. The drugs affect those parts of the
brain machine that process sensory data. The have the same kind of "unexpected"
effect as the "wrong" coin in the ticket machine, mentioned in chapter
1, which persuaded the machine to disgorge an entire roll of tickets. This possibility
was implicit in the mechanics of the ticket machine but was not intended to be
part of its function. The same goes for drugs and brains.
The is no hourglass
symmetry between mind and matter. To repeat an image from chapter 1, reality may
perhaps be a figment of our imagination, as some philosophers argue, but our imagination
is definitely a figment of reality.
John Cornwall
" Nature's Imagination:
The Frontiers of Scientific Vision, Oxford 1995. Essays from a September 1992
meeting:
" "Introduction. The scientist as rebel," Freeman
Dyson
" "Must mathematical physics be reductionist?" Roger
Penrose
" "Randomness in arithmetic and the decline and fall of
reductionism in pure mathematics," Gergory J. Chaitin
" "Theories
of Everything," John D. Barrow
" "Intertheoretic reduction:
a neuroscientists's gield guide," Paul M. Churchland and Patricia S. Churchland
" "Neural Darwinism: the brain as a selectional system," Gerald
M. Edelman and Giulio Tononi
" "A new vistion of the mind,"
Oliver Sacks
" "The limitless power of science," P. W. Atkins
" "Reductive megalomania," Mary Midgley
" "Artificial
intelligence and human dignity," Margaret A. Boden
" "On 'computabilism'
and physicalism: some subproblems," Hao Wang
" "Knowledge representation
and myth," W. F. Clocksin
" "Memory and the individual soul:
against silly reductionism," Gerald M. Edelman
Erik Davis
"
Techgnosis: Myth, Magic, and Mysticism in the Age of Information (Harmony 1998)
from p. 38:
"The powerful aura that today's advanced technologies
cast does not derive solely from their novelty or their mystifying complexity;
it also derives from their literal realization of the virtual projects willed
by the wizards and alchemists of an earlier age. Magic is technology's unconscious,
it own arational spell. Our modern technological world is not nature, but augmented
nature, super-nature, and the more intensely we probe its mutant edge of mind
and matter, the more our disenchanted productions will find themselves wrestling
with the rhetoric of the supernatural."
Mike Fortun
" Muddling
Through: Pursuing Science and Truths in the 21st Century, coauthored by Herbet
J. Bernstein. Counterpoint 1998.
"Muddling Through is a book about the
sciences in the late twentieth century and about the kind of sciences we need
for the twenty-first. It is a book about how the sciences make sense of the world
and provide sense to the world. Think of Muddling Through as the basic text for
a different kind of science literacy project, a project to reimagine and then
enact the sciences as operations of language and thought and as attempts, trials,
limited experiments involving things, ideas, and just about everything in between.
"This is also a book about politics (not policy) and culture - that is,
about how the sciences are made through arduous and diverse political processes.
This book is about how the sciences affect politics not only through technological
inventions but by generating the images and metaphors that we apply to every situation
and phenomenon we encounter, and by providing the blueprints we use to make and
legitimate crucial social decisions. The connnections between the sciences and
democratic pluralism need to be revitalized, through both new concepts and innovative
social forms."
Ian Hacking
" The Social Construction of What?
(Harvard, 1999)
from p. 68
... the science wars are founded upon, among
other things of a more political or social nature, profound and ancient philosophical
disputes.
Ralph Gun Hoy Siu
" The Tao of Science: An Essay on Western
Knowledge and Eastern Wisdom, (MIT 1957)
from pp. 136-137:
But modern
science is beginning to forget the labor of her birth and Galileo's revolt against
the scholastic trammels to establish "things as are and seen" in preference
to "things as abstracted and conceived." Resplendent in her attainments
and power, she is ascending the very same throne of the intellectual monarch she
deposed.
Science now appears to be dictating the intellectual fashions of
the day. If a plan is not prepared according to the scientific method, it is considered
unreliable. If a question cannot be tested by science, it is considered meaningless.
If traditional institutions are slow to adopt the scientific way, they are considered
backward. If a mode of life is not comprehendible by science, it is considered
old-fashioned. As a result of these intrusions, the certitude of purpose in the
scheme of things begins to waver. Means are being homogenized with ends.
Many
scientists are on the threshold of emulating theologians of the sixteenth century.
Some are beginning to develop a pugnacity that bespeaks a deep uncertainty of
brittle pride. Others are transgressing beyond their limited compass of competence.
Still others seem not to care a doit that the unitary purpose of culture is being
blunted and that the wholeness of meaning and the very tradition of a cooperative
society are being disintegrated. If encouraged along the current trends, science
may soon reach the point of diminishing usefulness to humanity. To retain her
contributing relevancy is an important problem of the twentieth century.
from
pp. 142-143:
As a result of her abstraction complex, science began to dissociate
her thoughts from the parent reality of mankind from which she sprang. She wanted
to be left alone to play with her artificial worlds, creating things and systems
that often do not harmonize with the scheme of life and upsetting the equilibrium
of the world in most explosive ways. For these reasons R. Guenon refers to modern
science as the "degenerate vestiges" of the ancient traditional knowledge.
Wiser scientists are beginning to realize that a specialist is but an abstraction
of man, a personality out of context. They are beginning to appreciate Toynbee's
conclusions that "there is no correlation between progress in technique and
progress in civilization." Their souls clamor in their native humility for
a return to the complete man. Yet to be men as men, they must cease being a particular
kind f men. They cannot be men as scientists. They must shake off their servitude
to the chains of abstracted and rational thought. They must control the scientific
implements, put them in their proper perspective and lose them in the intimacy
of their total experience as men.
Ecologies of Knowledge
edited by Susan
Leigh Star, SUNY 1995. Contents:
" "Science, Social Problems, and
Progressive Thought: Essays on the Tyranny of Science", Jennifer Croissant
and Sal Restivo
" "The Politics of Formal Representations: Wizards,
Gurus, and Organizational Complexity", Susan Leigh Star
" "Computerization
Movements and the Mobilization of Support for Computerization", Rob Kling
and C. Suzanne Iacono
" "Representation, Cognition, and Self: What
Hope for an Integration of Psychology and Sociology?", Steve Woolgar
"
"Research Materials and Reproductive Science in the United States, 1910-1940",
Adele E. Clarke
" Laboratory Space and the Technological complex: An
Investigation of Topical Contextures", Michael Lynch
" "Mixing
Humans and Nonhumans Together: The Sociology of a Door Closer", Bruno Latour
" "Engineering and Sociology in a Military Aircraft Project: A Network
Analysis of Technological Change", John Law and Michael Callon
"
"Ecologies of Action: Recombining Genes, Molecularizing Cancer, and Transforming
Biology", Joan H. Fujimura
John Ziman
" Public Knowledge: The
Social Dimension of Science, (Cambridge 1968)
" The Force of Knowledge:
The Scientific Dimension of Society, (Cambridge 1976)
" Reliable Knowledge:
An Exploration of the Grounds for Belief in Science, (Cambridge 1978)
"
Puzzles, Problems and Enigmas: Occasional Pieces on the Human Aspects of Science,
(Cambridge 1981)
" Prometheus Bound: Science in a Dynamic Steady State,
(Cambridge 1994)
" Of One Mind: The Collectivization of Science, (American
Institute of Physics 1995)
from p. 188:
Although we have no reason to
doubt the practical reliability of well-explored and well tested branches of the
natural sciences, we are also aware of the vast extent of our scientific ignorance
on most matters of real human significance. No philosopher now supports a "scientific
method" that can carry all before it in every field of knowledge. We must
always ask to see the credentials of whatever is offered to us as scientific truth,
look at how it is generated and validated, and make up our own minds whether it
is more convincing than what we might derive from practical experience, common
sense, personal insight, or social tradition.
" Real Science: What It
Is, and What It Means (Cambridge 2000)
from p. 4:
This new picture of
science is somewhat more complicated that the outmoded stereotype. It is not so
sharply defined. It does not claim total competence. It treats human knowledge
as a product of the natural world. It does not pretend to be impregnable against
thorough-going skepticism or cynicism. It calls for more modesty and tolerance
than scientists have customarily cultivated about themselves and their calling.
But it does provide stout intellectual and moral defence for science at the level
of ordinary human affairs - the level at which nothing is absolute or eternal,
but where we often forget that life is short, and feel passionately about pasts
that we have not personally experienced, or plan conscientiously for the future
welfare of people whom we shall never know.
Resources for Software Engineering
Computers
bring mathematical logic out into the big world. They got started in roughly the
1930's with Gödel, Turing, and Church making formal logic more precise by
providing a mechanical model. Now formal logic has become a major global industry,
contacting almost every facet of life, as the mechanical model has been incarnated
as semiconductor circuitry, miniaturized and replicated through photolithography.
The difficulties of creating a description of the world become more difficult
to sweep under the rug when the mechanical system embodies such formal precision.
The glitches in the description show up as computer systems that work poorly in
practise.
Nathaniel S. Borenstein
" Programming As If People Mattered
: Friendly Programs, Software Engineering, and Other Noble Delusions An exploration
of practical ways to manage the engineering process for more humanly beneficial
results.
Software Development and Reality Construction
Proceedings of a
conference held in 1988, published by Springer Verlag in 1992, edited by Christiane
Floyd, Heinz Züllighoven, Reinhard Budde, and Reinhard Keil-Slawik. Contents:
" "Human Questions in Computer Science", Christiane Floyd
"
"Learning from our Errors", Donald E. Knuth
" "The Technical
and the Human Side of Computer Science", Klaus-Peter Löhr
"
"Hermeneutics and Path", Joseph A. Goguen
" "Computing:
Yet Another Reality Construction", Rodney M. Burstall
" "How
Many Choices Do We Make? How Many Are Difficult?", Kristen Nygaard
"
"From Scientific Practise to Epistemological Discovery", Douglas T.
Ross
" "Self-Organization and Software Development", Heinz
von Foerster and Christiane Floyd
" "Software Development as Reality
Construction", Christiane Floyd
" "The Idea that Reality is
Socially Constructed", Bo Dahlbom
" "Scientific Expertise as
a Social Process", Klaus Amaan
" "How to Communicate Proofs
or Programs", Dirk Siefkes
" "Making Errors, Making Sense,
Making Use", John M. Carroll
" "Artifacts in Software Design",
Reinhard Keil-Slawik
" "The Denial of Error", Joseph A. Goguen
" "Toward a New Understanding of Data Modelling", Heinz K.
Klein and Kalle Lyytinen
" "A Reappraisal of Information Science",
Pentti Kerola and Jouni Similä
" "Perspectives and Metaphors
for Human-Computer Interaction", Susanne Maass and Horst Oberquelle
"
"Sortware Tools in a Programming Workshop", Reinhard Budde and Heinz
Züllighoven
" ""Soft Engines - Mass-Produced Software
for Working People?", Wolfgang Coy
" "Artificial Intelligence:
A Hermeneutic Defense", Thomas F. Gordon
" "Shared Responsibility:
A Field of Tension", Gro Bjerknes
" "A Subject-Oriented Approach
to Information Systems", Markku I. Nurminen
" "Anticipating
Reality Construction", Fanny-Michaela Reisin
" "On Controllability",
Wolfgang Dzida
" "Work Design for Human Development", Walter
Volpert
" "Truth and Meaning Beyond Formalism", Joseph A. Goguen
" "Informatics and Hermeneutics", Rafael Capurro
"
"Language and Software, or: Fritzl's Quest", Dafydd Gibbon
"
"Activity Theory as a Foundation for Design", Arne Raeithel
"
"Reflections on the Essence of Information", Klaus Fuchs-Kittowski
Joseph
Goguen
From "The Denial of Error," in Software Development and Reality
Construction , pp 193-202:
This paper claims that the modern world has developed
a kind of arrogance which is damaging the very projects that it seeks to sustain:
in proposing methodoligies to guarantee the absence of error, we deny the incredible
richness of our own experience, in which confusion and error are often the seeds
of creation; in this way, we limit our own creativity. [p] This arrogance is not
an isolated phenomenon that is found only in computer science. Indeed, I claim
that it arises in a natural way from our preoccupation with and immersion in science
and technology, which are strongly oriented toward control. ... A software development
project is not primarily a formal mathematical entity. Perhaps it is best seen
as a dialogical or linguistic process, an evolving organization of certain informational
structures, continually recreating itself by building, modifying, and reusing
these structures. ... Important avenues for further progress in Software Engineering
seem to be blocked by our inadequate understanding of the processes involved in
developing software systems. ... Although formal methods can be very powerful
when they are properly applied, they also have definite limitations, and formal,
rationalistic understanding is only one of many approaches to understanding. Intuition
and spiritual understanding are alternatives that seem more important in certain
ways.
William Kent
" Data and Reality: Basic Assumptions in Data
Processing Reconsidered. (North-Holland 1978)
from page 9:
We seem to
have little difficulty with the concept of "one person" despite changes
in appearance, personality, capabilities, and, above all, chemical composition.
(The proportions and structure - i.e., the chemical formulas - may not change
much, but the individual atoms and melecules are continually being replaced...
again illustrating an ambiguity between "same kind" and "same instance":
how rapidly is the chemical composition of your body changing?) When we speak
of the same person over a period of time, we certainly are not referring to the
same ensemble of atoms and molecules. What then is the "same person"?
We can only appeal to some vague intuition obout the "continuity" of
- something - through gradual change. The concept of "same person" is
so familiar and obvious that it is absolutely irritating no to be able to define
it. Definitions in terms of "soul" and "spirit" may be the
only true and humanisitic concepts, but, significantly, we don't know how to deal
with them in a computer-based information system. It is only when the notion of
"person" is pushed to some limit do we realize how imprecise the notion
is.
from p. 203:
In an absolute sense, there is no singular objective
reality. But we can share a common enough view of it for most of our working purposes,
so that reality does appear to be objective and stable.
But the chances of
acieving such a shared view become poorer when we try to encompass broader purposes,
and to involve more people. This is precisely why the question is becoming more
relevant today: the thrust of technology is to foster interaction among greater
numbers of people, and to integrate processes into monoliths serving wider and
wider purposes. It is in this environment that discrepencies in fundamental assumputions
will become increasingly exposed.
Jaron Lanier
" ONE HALF OF A MANIFESTO
" "There is nothing more gray, stultifying, or dreary than a life
lived inside the confines of a theory."
Research Methods in Information
Systems
Proceedings of colloquium held in 1984 titled, "Information Systems
Research: a doubtful science?", edited by Enid Mumford, Rudi Hirschheim,
Guy Fitzgerald, and Trevor Wood-Harper, published by Elsevier in 1985. Contents:
" "Information Systems Research Methodology: An Introduction to
the Debate", G. Fitzgerald, R. A. Hirschheim, E. Mumford and A. T. Wood-Harper
" "Information Systems Epistemology: An Historical Perspective",
Rudi Hirschheim
" "Acquiring Knowledge of Information Systems -
Research in a Methodological Quagmire", Hans-Erik Nissen
" "Contextualist
Research and the Study of Organizational Change Processes", Andrew M. Pettigrew
" "Socio-Technical Design, Trade Union Strategies and Action Research",
Ake Sandberg
" "Research Methodologies and MIS Research", A.
Milton Jenkins
" "Development, Application and Enrichment of STROBE:
Refinement of an Observational Tool for the Information Analyst", Kenneth
Kendall and Julie Kendall
" "The Poverty of Scientism in Information
Systems", Heinz K. Klein and Kalle Lyytinen
" "Research Methods
in Information Systems: Using Action Research", Trevor Wood-Harper
"
"Phenomenology: A Preferred Approach to Research on Information Systems",
Richard J. Boland, Jr.
" "Selection of a Research Method",
Lyn Antill
" "The Critical Theory of Jurgen Habermas as a Basis
for a Theory of Information Systems", Kalle Lyytinen and Heinz K. Klein
"
""Perception and Deceptions: Issues for Information Systems Research",
Kathy Brittain White
" "The Need for Longitudinal Designs in the
Study of Computing Environments", Nicholas P. Vitalari
" "In
Search of a Paradigm for Information Systems Research", Robert D. Galliers
" "Two Research Methodologies for Studying User Development of Data
Systems", Per Flensburg
" "Research People Problems: Some Advice
to a Student", Enid Mumford
Brian Cantwell Smith
" On the Origin
of Objects, MIT Press 1996.
from p. vii-viii:
Having spent more than twenty-five
years working in the trenches of practicing computer science, in a long-term effort
to develop an empirically responsible theory of computation, I had never met such
a logically pure entity, never met such a lapidary individual thing.
from
p. 3:
This book introduces a new metaphysics - a philosophy of presence -
that aims to steer a path between the Scylla of naive realism and the Charybdis
of pure constructivism. The goal is to develop an integral account that retains
the essential humility underlying each tradition: a form of epistemic deference
to the world that underlies realism, and a respect for the constitutive human
involvement in the world that underwrites constructivism. The proposal is also
intended to be neutral with respoect to (a late twentieth-century update of) C.
P. Snow's famous two culutres - serving equally as a foundation for the academic,
intellectual, and technological, on the one hand, and for the curious, the moral,
the erotic, the political, the artistic, and the sheerly obstreperous, on the
other.
from pp. 288-289
Objects are not stabilized only through acts of
disconnected focusing, in other words. Nor are they stabilized merely in virtue
of their own integrity or achievement, or even of the two phenomena together.
They are also stabilized by force, through the travails of those who register
them. And not solely through the efforts of individuals, or even institutions,
but with the full complicity of the surrounding community of practice.
Gerald
M. Weinberg
Practical insights into managing systems engineering.
"
Quality Software Management in four volumes:
13. Systems Thinking
14.
First-Order Measurement
15. Congruent Action
16. Anticipating Change
"
Exploring Requirements : Quality Before Design coauthored by Donald Gause.
"
On the Design of Stable Systems, (Wiley 1979) coauthored by Daniela Weinberg.
from pp. 67-69:
Now we can see what really "distinguishes [physics
and chemistry] from biology." There is nothing "inherent" or "legitimate"
in their use of statistics - that is, in their use of means or of types. In nature,
we very rarely find a bar of pure gold or a solution of pure glucose. In fact,
we very rarely find "pure" undifferentiated anything, since purity is
one of those observer's fictions. The physicist has to work very, very hard to
get her "pure" gold, and even then she will have a mixture of isotopes,
unless she works very much harder.
The reason we don't speak of "physical
variation" is that the physicist has chosen not to work with naturally occurring
systems, but, rather, with the products of her laboratory. Most of her time in
that laboratory is spent eliminating the variation and keeping it eliminated.
Moreover, she must artificially ensure the survival of each aggregate, for a lump
of pure gold, and especially a solution of pure glucose, would not survive long
without the active participation of the scientist.
...
The reductionist
- interested in "law" - emphasizes the sameness; the antireductionist
- interested in "life" - emphasizes the difference. If the reductionist
goes to the extreme, his laws are about systems that have zero probability of
being observed; while if the antireductionist goes to his extreme, his systems
also have zero probability of being observed - for if a system is truly unique,
our minds cannot deal with it at all. In the first case the system does not exist,
while in the second we have no way of observing its existence.
" An Introduction
to General Systems Thinking
Resources
for Mathematics
Jon Barwise
" Situations and Attitudes, (MIT 1983),
coauthored by John Perry.
from p. ix:
In recent years a different perspective,
one we associate with Thomas Reid, has been revitalized by the work of the psychologist
J. J. Gibson and a famous paper by Hilary Putnam, "The meaning of 'Meaning.'"
Gibson, studying the coordinated perception and action of animals, found much
more information in the environment (and so less work to be done by the animal
brain, or mind) than the traditional view of perception admitted; and Putnam's
paper, we think, shows that there is much more meaning and information in the
world and less in the head than the traditional view of meaning assumed. From
these two complementary movements a new realism has emerged, Ecological Realism,
a view that finds meaning located in the interaction of living things and their
environment. What began for us as an exercise in technical philosohpy, reworking
Frege, undoing his mistake, led us step by inevitable step to working out the
beginnings of a theory of meaning implicit in this new realism.
" Vicious
Circles: On the Mathematics of Non-Wellfounded Phenomena, (CSLI 1996), coauthored
with Lawrence Moss.
from p. 5:
In certain circles, it has been thought
that there is a conflict between circular phenomena, on the one hand, and mathematical
rigor, on the other. This belief rests on two assumptions. One is that anything
mathematically rigorous must be reducible to set theory. The other assumption
is that the only coherent conception of set precludes circularity. As a result
of these two assumptions, it is not uncommon to hear circular analyses of philosophical,
linguistic, or comutational phenomena attacked on the grounds that they conflict
with one of the basic axioms of mathematics. But both assumptions are mistaken
and the attack is groundless.
" The Logic of Distributed Systems, (Cambridge
1997), coauthored by Jerry Seligman.
from p. 219:
We have required that
our regimentations live in the field of real numbers. An alternative suggestion
would allow them to live in non-Archimedian fields, like the fields of nonstandard
real numbers. One could then allow the tolerance to be infinitesimal, and sorites
numbers could be infinite. This goes along with the discovery in recent years
that nonstandard analysis often gives an elegant way to model the differences
between the very small and the very large.
Shaughan Lavine
" Understanding
the Infinite (Harvard 1994)
from p. 133:
When combined with Skolem's arguments,
those of von Neumann amount to a devastating criticism of our present-day axiomatic
foundations of mathematics on the basis of set theory: Those foundations rely
on a notion of proof, which requires a notion of finitude for its definition.
But, once we specify the notion of definiteness, our axioms enable us to show
that the definition of finitude they provide is an iniadequate foundation for
the notion of proof. ... The criticism is not directed at the practice of using
proofs, a practice that we can certainly acquire without having a theory of proofs
or an adequate characterization of finitude. In practice all we need in the way
of a theory of finitude is the recognition that any proof we actually encounter
in completed form is finite, which is very far from a complete characterization
of what it is to be finite. The criticism is directed at a certain kind of attempt
to characterize or define what the practice allows in the way of proofs. The attempt
fails.
Raymond Smullyan
Smullyan relates the puzzles confronted in mathematical
logic to the broader scope of living.
" 5000 B.C. and Other Philosophical
Fantasies
" Lady or the Tiger? And Other Logic Puzzles Including a Mathematical
Novel That Features Godel's Great Discovery
" The Tao Is Silent
"
This Book Needs No Title : A Budget of Living Paradoxes, (Prentice Hall 1980,
Simon & Schuster 1986)
from pp. 97-98:
"Are human beings like
mountains and streams?" This is a profound question, and there seems to be
remarkably divergent opinion on the matter! I think may people would say, "Of
course they are different!" Expecially those brought up in a Jewish or Christian
tradition would say: "Humans are alive. They have souls. They are rational.
They have free will and make choices. They are capable of good and evil; they
have moral responsibility; they are capable of sinning," etc., tec. On the
other hand, there are those ultra-mechanistic types - often in the computer sciences
- who say that human beings are basically like mountains and streams; they are
both causally determined mechanisms. The human being (they say) may be a more
complicated kind of machine but is a machine nevertheless and subject to exactly
the same physical laws which govern the behavior of mountains and streams. Therefore
human beings are like mountains and streams.
But what a ghastly, perverted
way of looking at it! I don't know which of these two viewpoints I find more horrible!
The first empasizes that aspect of religion I have always hated. The second is
completely inhuman. I also tend to think of humans - at their best - as being
like mountains and streams, but for such different reasons! In the first place,
I don't think of humans as machines. Second, I don't think of the universe as
a mchine; I think of it as an organism rather than a mechanism. Even if it is
perfectly decribable, using purely mechanical and electromagnetic laws, I still
think of it as an organism rather than a mechanism. And I think of mountains and
streams as part of the organism of the cosmos, and a very beautiful part of that.
And since I like to think of human beings as also beautiful, I therefore like
to think of them - at their best - as being like mountains and streams.
"
What Is the Name of This Book? : The Riddle of Dracula and Other Logical Puzzles